• Non ci sono risultati.

Auditing, disclosure, and verification in decentralized decision problems

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Auditing, disclosure, and verification in decentralized decision problems"

Copied!
16
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

ContentslistsavailableatScienceDirect

Journal

of

Economic

Behavior

&

Organization

jo u r n al ho me p ag e :ww w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / j e b o

Auditing,

disclosure,

and

verification

in

decentralized

decision

problems

Luca

Anderlini

a,∗

,

Dino

Gerardi

b

,

Roger

Lagunoff

a

aGeorgetownUniversity,USA bCollegioCarloAlberto,Italy

a

r

t

i

c

l

e

i

n

f

o

Articlehistory:

Received5February2016

Receivedinrevisedform30August2016 Accepted9September2016

Availableonline30September2016 JELclassification: C73 D63 D72 D74 H11 Keywords: Auditing Disclosure Agencybias Ideologicalbias

a

b

s

t

r

a

c

t

Westudytherelativeperformanceofdisclosureandauditingindecentralizedinstitutions. Weconsidertheinformationtransmissionproblembetweentwodecisionmakerswhotake actionsinsequenceattwodecisiondates.Thefirstdecisionmakerhasprivateinformation aboutastateofnaturethatisrelevantforbothdecisions,andsendsamessagetothe second.Theseconddecisionmakercancommittoonlyobservethemessage(disclosure),or canretaintheoptiontoobservetheactionofthefirstdecisionmaker(auditing)or,atsome cost,toverifythestate.Inequilibrium,stateverificationwillneveroccurandthesecond decisionmakereffectivelychoosesbetweenauditinganddisclosure.

Whenthemisalignmentinpreferencesreflectsanagencybias–abiasinadecision maker’sownactionrelativetothatoftheother–thentheseconddecisionmakerchooses toauditinequilibrium.Whenthemisalignmentinpreferencesreflectsanideologicalbias –onedecisionmakerprefersallactionstobebiasedrelativetotheotherdecisionmaker –then,foralargeenoughmisalignment,theseconddecisionmakerchoosesdisclosurein equilibrium.Ourresultsindicatethattheabilitytocommittoforegotheaudithasvaluein thelattercase.

©2016ElsevierB.V.Allrightsreserved.

1. Introduction

Inanyongoingorganizationorsocietytherearetwoprimarywaysinwhichinformationisrevealed.Oneisdisclosure– transmissionofinformationbytheinformedpartiestouninformedreceivers.1Disclosureconsistsofallformsof

manufac-turedtransmissionincludingoralandwritten(files,archives,etc.)communication.Theactofdisclosinginformationmayor maynotbeobligatory.2Thekeyisthatitscontentcanbefreelychosenbytheinformedsender.

夽 Apreviousdraftwascirculatedunderthetitle:“DoActionsSpeakLouderthanWords?Auditing,Disclosure,andVerificationinOrganizations.”Wewish tothankTomGresik,anAssociateEditor,andtwoanonymousrefereesfortheirhelpfulcommentsandsuggestions.Wealsothankseminarparticipants atJohnsHopkins,NorthCarolina,PUC(Chile),HKUST,theIADB,UniversidadAlbertoHurtado,Vanderbilt,andtheMidwestTheoryMeetingsatIndiana University.AllthreeauthorsaregratefultotheNationalScienceFoundationforfinancialsupport(GrantSES-0617789).Someoftheworkwascarriedout whileLucaAnderliniwasvisitingEIEFinRome.Hegratefullyacknowledgestheirgeneroushospitality.

∗ Correspondingauthorat:GeorgetownUniversity,37thandOStreetsNW,Washington,DC20057,USA. E-mailaddress:luca@anderlini.net(L.Anderlini).

1Noticethatwhileweusethetermdisclosureassynonymouswithcheaptalk,ithasalsobeenusedintheliteratureasrevelationofinformationthatis verifiablebythereceiver.

2Recordkeepingrequirementsinfirmsfitthisdefinition.

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2016.09.002

(2)

Theotherformofrevelationisdiscretionaryauditing–theattemptbytheuninformedpartytoinvestigateorverifythe informationinsomefashion.AuditingmaytakeplaceundertheguiseofaformalprocessorinstitutionsuchastheGeneral AccountabilityOfficeintheU.S.government,oritmaytaketheformofaninformalmonitoringarrangementinacollective actionproblem.

Thispaperstudiestherelativeperformanceofdisclosureandauditingindecentralizeddecisionsettings.Inthesesettings, itisoftendecisionmakersthemselveswhomakechoicesaboutwhichofthetwoinformationchannelsisbest.

Infirms,forinstance,differentmanagersarepromotedtokeydecision-makingpostsovertime.Itisstandardpractice foracurrentmanagerialteamwithinside knowledgetoprovideadetailedprospectusofthecompany’soverallhealth periodically.Evenso,itspolicies,expenditures,andacquisitionsmayalsobeauditedtoprovidesomeexternalverification toshareholdersandsubsequentgenerationsofmanagers.

Politicalsystemsoperateinmuchthesameway.Rivalpoliticalpartiesvieforpowerovertime.Arulingpoliticalparty holdssomeinsideinformation(forinstance,knowledgeoftheeffectsofaparticularregulation)andisrequiredtodisclose whatitknowsorobserves.Arivalpartyeventuallyreachespowerandmustthenchoosetoeitheraccepttheoutgoingparty’s wordsorinsteadinvestigatetheoutgoingparty’spoliciesanddecisions.

Otherexamplesincludecommonpoolproblemsinwhichuserswithcurrentaccesstotheresourcemustdecideonthe bestmeanstoextractinformationaboutthestockfromearlierusers,andregulatoryenvironmentsinwhichregulatorsmust decideonhowstructurereportingrequirements.

Withtheseexamplesinmind,wepositatwo-periodpolicysettingmodelthatattemptstocapturesomeofthekeytrade offsinthechoiceoftransmissionmechanism.Weassumethatthepolicyateachdateischosenbyadistinctdecisionmaker. Disclosureisassumedtotaketheextremeformofcheaptalk,whileauditingtakestheextremeformofbeingabletodirectly observetheactionstakenbyothers.Inperiod1,theinitialdecisionmaker–DM1(the“sender”)–choosesanaction(a “policy”)andacheap-talkmessageafterprivatelyobservingtherealizationofanunderlyingstatevariablethataffectsthe preferencesofbothDMs.Inperiod2,theseconddecisionmaker–DM2(the“receiver”)–choosesapolicy.

ThechoicesofpossibleinformationchannelsopentoDM2areasfollows.Shecanchoosetocommittoonlyobserve DM1’smessagebeforeDM1takesanyactionorsendshismessage.Werefertothisasacommitmenttorelyondisclosure. ThedecisionbyDM2ofwhetherornottorelyondisclosureisobservedbyDM1whothenchooseshispolicy.IfDM2chooses nottocommit,sheretainstheoptiontoobserveDM1’saction,whichwerefertoasauditing,ordirectlyverifythestate– referredtosimplyasverification.Forsimplicity,auditingisassumedtobecostlessandstateverificationhasavanishing small(lexicographic)cost.3Onceperiod2arrives,DM2isinchargeoftheorganizationandheractionisthentaken.

Misalignedpreferencesbetweenthetwotemporallyseparatedagents(e.g.,twomanagerialteams,twopoliticalparties, ortworesourceusers)distortincentivesawayfromprofit-maximizing,orwelfaremaximizingpolicies.Theeffectofthis misalignmenthereisthatfulldisclosuredoesnotoccur.Inthissenseoursetupisrelatedtotheclassiccheaptalkenvironment inCrawfordandSobel(1982)(henceforth“CS”).TheirsenderisourDM1,whileDM2istheirreceiver.UnlikeintheCS environment,policydecisionsherearemadebybothplayersandthereceivermaychoosetoauditbeforetakingherown decision.

Weaskwhendisclosurewillbeused,andwheninsteadorganizationsrelyonauditing,orevenverification,inequilibrium. Theanswerisnuancedanddependsontheparticularcharacteristicsoftheorganization.

Ourfirstresult,Proposition1,showsthatDM2willneverchoosethedirectverificationoptioninequilibrium.Intuitively, ifDM1expectsthestatetobeverifieddirectly,hewouldchoosehismostpreferredfirstperiodpolicytailoredtothestate. Butbecausehispolicywouldfullyrevealthestate,theuninformedDM2wouldthenswitchtothelesscostlypolicyaudit. Thisisshowninanypurestrategyequilibrium,butwelaterverifythatitholdsgenerically(inthelevelofbias/misalignment) formixedstrategyequilibriaaswell.4

AsaresultofProposition1,DM2’seffectivechoiceisbetween“words”(disclosure)andthe“actions”(policyaudit)ofher predecessor,DM1.Thechoicebetweenwordsandactionsultimatelydependsonthewedgeinpreferencesbetweenthetwo parties.Werefertothismisalignmentasthe“bias”(followingCS)andexaminethefollowingtwocanonicalcases.

Inthecaseofideologicalbias,thefirstdecisionmakerDM1alwayspreferssystematicallyhigherpoliciesthanDM2, regardlessofwhichpartychoosesorwhichperiodthechoiceismade.Theideologicalbiasesarisenaturallyinpoliticswhere competitionbetweenideologicallydifferentiatedpartiestakesplace.

Ideologicalbiascontrastswiththecaseofagencybiaswherebytheactivedecisionmakerprefersahigher(orlower)policy thanhiscounterpart,thepassivestakeholder.ThismeansthatDM1(DM2)prefers,say,ahigheractioninperiod1(period2) thanDM2(DM1).Arguably,manyprivatefirmsconformtothiscasesincethefuturedecisionmaker(DM2)isoftenselected internallyfromexistingmanagement,andthepreviousmanagerholdsstockoptionsthatincentivizeshisfuturedecisions. Thesetwoformsofbiasgiverisetoquitedifferenttransmissionprotocols.Withagencybias,DM2willgenerallychoosea policyaudit.However,underlargeenoughideologicalbias,DM2willcommitinadvancetouseonlythedisclosedinformation. Inotherwords,wefindthatunderideologicalbias,theuninformedpartywillrelysolelyontheinformedparty’scheaptalk inequilibriumandthusforegoallsubsequentauditandstateverificationopportunities.

3 Theassumptionofcostlesspolicyauditsisshowntobewithoutlossofgenerality.Alltheresultsgothroughifauditscostsaresmall.Ourmainresult (Proposition3(i))goesthroughwitharbitraryauditingcosts.SeeSection5foradetaileddiscussion.

(3)

Togainsomeintuitionfortheseresults, weobservefirstthatequilibriainwhichDM2reliesonlyonmessageswill resemblethoseinstandardcheaptalkmodels(e.g.CS).Thatis,whileDM1can,inprinciple,reportfalseinformation,she choosesnottoinequilibrium.Instead,thesender’smessageispartially,butnotfully,informative.Thelackoffulldisclosure isofcoursebadforDM2.Incontrast,whenapolicyauditoccursinequilibrium,DM1chooseshisactiontakingintoaccount bothitsdirectpayoffeffect,drivenbythebias,anditssignalingvaluedrivenbyDM1’spreferencesoverDM2’sactioninthe secondperiod.

Whenthewedgebetweenpreferencestakestheformofanagencybias,thesetwoeffectsroughlyoffsetoneanother, therebymitigatingtheeffectofthesender’sbias.However,inthecaseofideologicalbias,thedirectpayoffeffectandthe signalingvaluereinforceoneanother;bothinduceactionsthataretoolargefortherecipient.Ifthereinforcedeffectofthe biasislargeenough,theauditbecomesundesirableforDM2whothenavoidsitinequilibrium.Infact,weshowthatforgoing theauditinganddirectverificationoptionsinfavorofdisclosureisnotjustpreferablefortherecipientunderideological bias,butitisParetoimprovingforallpartiesiftheideologicalbiasislargeenough.

AcriticalpartoftheargumentisthatDM2cancommitinadvancetoforegooratleastlimitthescopeofadiscretionary audit.Tosomeextent,thiscanbeviewedasasimplifyingassumptionsincethecommitmenttoforegoauditingisshownto bepreferredbybothdecisionmakersinmostcases.Thecommitmentbecomesinstitutionalizedwhenaconsensusexists amongallthepartiesexante.Standardcorporatepolicy,forinstance,placesauditingauthorityinthehandsofthefirm’s boardofdirectors,ratherthantheCEO.5 Governmentsmakeallowancesaswelltopreventpublicauditsforreasonsof

nationalsecurity.

Naturally,insomecasescommitmentisnotalwayspossible.Theresultsofthepaperinformthesecasesaswell:without commitment,discretionaryauditingwilloccurmakingallpartiesworseoffunderalargeenoughideologicalbias.Atthis pointthelossofwelfarerelativetothedisclosureregimemaywellbecomeapparenttotheparticipants,butitsimplyistoo latetoavoidit.

Inourviewthisisatleastpartofthereasonwhy“audits”inthepoliticalsphereareoftenviewedas“partisanwitch hunts”where“allactorsinvolvedinaccountabilityprocessesuseavarietyofstrategiestoarguetheircaseandapportion blame”(Boinetal.,2008).A“witchhunt”ofthistypecanbeusedtouncoverembarrassingfactsaboutone’spoliticalrival. Inthelanguageofthemodel,themorepreciseistheembarrassinginformation,theeasieritisfortheinvestigatingpartyto implementitsidealpolicychoice.

Indeed, the frequency of partisan investigations is an indication that institutional commitments to avoid audit-ing/investigatingaremoredifficultinpoliticalsystems.

“Partisaninvestigationshavehistoricallybeenapoxonbothhouses[intheU.S.Congress]–embarrassingthe inves-tigatorsasmuchastheinvestigatedandwoundingthemajorityparty.[...]Toooften,investigativehearingsturnout tobeflightsofvanityforacommittee’smemberstospeechifyandhumiliatewitnesses.”–Goldberg(2010)

Thedestructivenatureofsuchinvestigationssuggestsaparadox.Infirms(whereagencybiasisprevalent),commitmentto forgoauditingmaybepossiblethoughunnecessarysinceauditswillalwaysbechoseninequilibriumregardlessofwhether commitmentispossible.Inpolitical systems,auditsoftenassumetheformofapartisaninvestigation.Inthis casethe commitmenttoforgoauditingwouldbechoseniffeasibleandwouldinfactbepreferableforallpartiesifthebiasislarge enough.Unfortunately,commitmentsofthistypearenotusuallycodifiedinpoliticalsystemsandmaythusbeinfeasible.

Theremainderofthepaperisorganizedasfollows.Section2discussesrelatedliterature.Section3setsoutthemodel.In Section4wecharacterizeequilibriaunderbothideologicalbiasandagencybias.Section5examinestherobustnessofthe mainresults,includingtheextensiontomixedstrategies.Section6concludeswithabriefdiscussionoftheaccountability systemsfoundinfirms,polities,andinformalcollectiveactionscenarios.AllproofsarerelegatedtoanAppendixtothe paper.Aprefixof“A”inthenumberingofequationsandsoonindicatesthattherelevantitemcanbefoundinAppendix.

2. Relatedliterature

Weexaminetheequilibriumchoiceofdisclosure,auditing,ordirectverificationbytheuninformedagent.Withsome exceptions(discussedbelow)mostoftheliteratureexaminesoneofthesetransmissionmechanisms,butdonotavailall theoptionstothemodeledagents.

Thereisawellestablishedliteratureon(costly)stateverificationbeginningwithTownsend(1979)(seeBoltonand Dewatripont,2005forfurtherreferences).Bywayofcomparison,therelevantfeatureinourmodelisthatstateverification doesnotariseinequilibriumwhenauditinganddisclosureareavailable,evenwhenverificationcostsaresmall.

DisclosureisthemainfocusofthecheaptalkcommunicationliteraturebeginningwithCS.6Thepresentpapercontains

elementsofdynasticcheaptalkreminiscentofSpector(2000)andAnderlinietal.(2012)(AGL)whichexaminetheeffectsof biasamongmultipledecisionmakersandtheincentivestodisclosethecontentsofone’sobjectivesignals(viacheaptalk) toothersinthetemporalchain.Inthesepapers,cheaptalk(disclosure)wastheonlyoptionfortransmittinginformation; neitherauditingordirectverificationwereavailabletotheuninformedagents.

5See[13].

(4)

ConditionallyonDM2notcommittingtodisclosure,thepresentmodelisconnectedtothevastliteratureonsignaling startedbySpence(1973),sinceauditinginvolvestheverificationofpayoffrelevantdecisions.Amodelrelatedtooursin thesignalinggenrecomesfromCarrilloandMariotti(2000)who examineasingleagentproblemwithpresent-biased preferences.Giventhebias,theirmodelmaybere-interpretedasamultipleagentdecisionproblem–asinthepresent model.Theirfocusison“voluntaryignorance,”i.e.,when/whetheranagentchoosestostoplearning.Inasense,thepresent modelalsoconcernsvoluntaryignorance–inthiscasebythereceiverwhomightchoosetocommittodisclosureandhence notto“learn”fromthesender.DaughetyandReinganum(2010)focusonarelatedquestionfromasocialwelfareperspective. Theyexamineaplanner’schoiceofprotocolinapublicgoodsprovisionproblembetweenprivacyrightsofanindividualand thesocialbenefitofexposingfreeriders.Our“wordsversusactions”tradeoffsomewhatresemblestheir“privacyversus publicinformation”trade-offeventhoughthereisno(cheaptalk)communicationinthelatter.

Anumberofpapershavecomparedoutcomeswhendifferenttypesofobservationtechnologiesarevaried.Prat(2005)

comparesdifferentmodelsinwhichaprincipalcanobserveeithertheactiondirectlyorinsteadanoisysignal.Otherpapers haveexamineddifferenttypesofcommunicationprotocolsthatmaybechosenbythesender.Austen-SmithandBanks (2000)andKartik(2007)allowthesendertochooseamonganarrayofbothcostlessandcostlymessages,thelatterreferred toas“moneyburning.”Theirresultsdemonstratehowtheprecisionofcheaptalkincreaseswiththeadditionofthemoney burningoption.KaramychevandVisser(2011)goastepfurtheringivingafullcharacterizationoftheoptimalexante equilibriumforthesenderinthemodelwithbothcheaptalkandmoneyburning.Kartik(2009)incorporateslyingcosts intothecheaptalkmodeltherebyturningcheaptalkintocostlysignaling.Heshowsthatequilibriaexistexhibitingfull separationincertainregionsofthetypespace,somethingthatisnotpossibleinthestandardCSmodelwithacontinuum oftypes.

Ourpaperdiffersfromtheseinthatweexaminethesignalingvalueofpoliciesratherthanthatofpuremoneyburning. Inthissense,thepresentpaperismorerelatedtoDaughetyandReinganum(2008)whostudytheendogenouschoiceof protocolbyfirmsthatattempttorevealqualityoftheirproducts.Intheirmodel,afirmcandisclosequalitythroughdirect claims,oritcansignalqualitythroughitsproductchoices.

Themaindifferencebetweenthesepapersandoursisthatweplacethechoiceofcommunicationprotocolinthehandsof thereceiverratherthanthesenderoraplanner.Whileprotocoldecisionsbythesenderarequitenaturalinamarketsettings –firmsvisavisconsumers–studiedbyDaughetyandReinganum(2008)andAusten-SmithandBanks(2000)amongothers, wethinkitquitenaturalthatthereversewouldbelikelywithinfirmsandgovernmentswheredynasticconsiderationsplaya role.Inthesecases,theactorsfeartheirpoliciesmaybeundonebyfuturedecisionmakersiftheinformationwererevealed. Hencetheiractionswouldnotordinarilycometolightunlessanexplicitauditmakesitthecase.

3. Themodel

TherearetwoDecisionMakers–DM1andDM2.Thefirsthasdecisionauthorityattimet=1andthesecondattimet=2. TheactionschosenbythetwoDMsinthetwotimeperiodsaredenotedbya1 ∈Randa2 ∈Rrespectively.

3.1. Payoffs

Thesymbol ∈Rdenotesthevalueofastateofnaturethatisdrawnonceandforallfromastrictlypositivecontinuous densityfdefinedonthereallineR.Thestateisdrawnbeforeanythingelsetakesplace.

Thetwodecisionmakersaredifferentiatedbyabiasparameterb>0.Thisparameteristhesourceofthepreference misalignmentbetweenthetwoDMs.Hence,itisthekeydriverofallequilibriumdecisionsinthemodel.Weconsidertwo canonicalcases.

ThefirstwecallIdeologicalBias,withpreferencesofDM1andDM2,respectively,givenby

V1=−(a1−−b)2−(a2−−b)2, and V2=−(a1−)2−(a2−)2 (1)

Here,theidealpolicyofDM1ineachperiodt=1,2isat=+bwhereastheidealpolicyforDM2isat=.WerefertoDM1as

being“biased”inbothperiodssincehisidealpolicyis“distorted”upwardbyb.7

WetermthesecondcanonicalcaseAgencyBias,withpreferencesofDM1andDM2,respectively,givenby

V1=−(a1−−b)2−(a2−)2, and V2=−(a1−)2−(a2−−b)2 (2)

Underagencybias,thepreferencemisalignmentisdrivenbytherolethateachDMhasineachperiod:activepolicymaker orpassivestakeholder.EachactiveDMisbiasedfortheactionthatcorrespondstotheperiodinwhichheistheactivepolicy maker,andunbiasedwhenheisa“passivestakeholder.”Hence,DMtideallypreferspolicyat=+bineachperiodt=1,2,

whereasDM( /=t)ideallyprefersat=.Ourterminologyinthiscaseismotivatedbythefactthatagencyproblemsarise

fromthemisalignmentofpreferencesbetweensomeonewhoactuallycontrolsapayoff-relevantvariable(theagent,orthe

7 Ofcourse,the“bias”labelisrelative.Moreover,theactualdirectionofthepreferencemisalignmentDM1’sidealpointislargerthanDM2’sis inessential.Wecouldallowforb<0.

(5)

activeDMineachperiodinourmodel)andapassivestakeholderwhoisaffectedbythechoicebuthasnodirectcontrol overit(theprincipal,or,inourmodel,DM2inperiod1andDM1inperiod2).

Ourterminologyisintendedtocaptureinherentincentiveconflictsinvariouscollectivedecisionsettings.Asastylized representation,ideologicalbiascanbefoundinpoliticalinstitutionsinwhichanoutgoingpoliticalpartyhassystematically differentpolicypreferencesthanitsnewlyelectedrival.Agencybiascanbefoundinfirmsinwhichamanager’spreferences aremisalignedwithhisorhersuccessororpredecessor,andDM2isselectedinternallyfromexistingmanagement.This newmanager,moreover,willhavepreferencesovertheuseofmanagerialperks(sayprivatejets),whileapastmanager whoholdsstockoptionsawardedduringhistenureasamanageronlyhaspreferencesformanagerialactionsthatinduce stock-appreciation.Theagencybiascasecanalsoapplytopoliticiansprovidedtheyareprimarilyoffice-motivatedrather thanideologicallydriven.Bothtypesbiascanbefoundininformalgroupsthatcoalescetosolvecollectionactionproblems.8

ThebiasesofthethetwoDMsinthetwoperiodsinthetwocanonicalcaseswehaveidentifiedarerepresented schemat-icallybelow.

(3) Notethatineithertheideologicalortheagencybiascase,asb→0theconflictbetweentheplayersvanishes.

3.2. Information,auditing,anddisclosure

Inthissubsection,weintroducetheformalauditingmodel.Thefocusisonhowthedegreeofconflict–asrepresented herebyb–distortstheincentivesofdecisionmakersateachdecisiondate.

Crucially,weassumethatneitherthestatenorthefirstperiodpolicyisautomaticallyobservedbyDM2.Specifically, thestateandthefirstperiodpolicya1areknownonlytoDM1,unlessDM2makesitapointtoverifythem.DM2therefore

assumespowerint=2knowingonlythatisrealizedfromacontinuousstrictlypositivedensityfdefinedonR.

Afterobservingandchoosinghispolicya1,theinformedagentDM1choosesamessagem∈Rthatcaninprinciplebe

usedtocommunicateor“disclose”somethingaboutthevalueofthestate.WerefertomessagemasDM1’sdisclosure statement.This,aswediscussedearlier,cantakeeitheroralorwrittenform.

Obviously,ifthedisclosurestatementfullyrevealedthestate,thenDM2wouldhavenoreasontoinvestigateor other-wiseexpendanyefforttoverifytheinformation.However,thebiascreatesamisalignmentinpreferencesoverthesecond periodpolicy.Hence,justasinthewellknowncheaptalkenvironments,themessagebyDM1willneverbefullyinformative. Knowingthisinadvance,theuninformedDM2hasachoicebeforeanypoliciesordisclosurestatementsareundertaken. ShecanchoosetorelyexclusivelyonDM1’smessageandtherebyforgoanyattempttoverifytheinformation.Alternatively, shecanholdopentheoptiontoseekadditionalinformationlateronafterthepoliciesanddisclosureoccurred.

Formally,welet∈{0,1}denotethe“commitment”choiceofDM2.Thechoice=1denotesthecommitmentbyDM2 toforgobothapolicyauditandstateverificationandhencetorelyonmalone,while=0denotes“keepingonesoptions open.”Choosing=0,DM2choosestoexercisediscretionaryauthorityatalaterdateoverwhatinformationshewillseek.

Iftheuninformedagentoptsfordiscretionaryauthority(=0),shesubsequentlyhasthreechoices,i.e.,threemethods ofobtaininginformationafterDM1’sdecisions.DM2can(i)stillchoosenottoaudit,andthereforerelyonlyonthemessage (wedenotethischoicebyNAfor“noaudit”),(ii)undertakeacostlessaudittoverifythepolicychoicea1ofDM1(wedenote

thischoicebyPA,for“policyaudit”),or(iii)undertakeacostlyaudittoverifythestatedirectly(wedenotethischoicebySV, for“stateverification”).Tosimplify,weassumethatbothSVandPAare“perfect”inthesensethatSVfullyrevealsthestate ,whilePAfullyrevealsthefirstperiodpolicychoicea1.Weletthechoiceacrossthesethreepossibilitiesbedenotedbyd

sothat

d∈{NA,PA,SV} (4)

Otherthingsequal,DM2wouldsurely(weaklyatleast)preferStateVerificationoveraPolicyAuditsincethestate,not theprioraction,isrelevanttoherpolicychoiceinperiod2.Ontheotherhand,theactofverifyingthestatedirectlymay bedifficultorcostlyinmanycommonsituations.Moreover,thefirstperiodpolicy,whilehavingnodirecteffectonthe

8Oneexamplesuggestedtousbyarefereeconcernsacommonpoolproblemwithanunknownresourcestock.Initialusersofthestock(e.g.,fisherman) observeinformationaboutthestock(thefishingthatdaywasgood)whichcanbecommunicatedormonitored(audited)bysubsequentresourceusers. Agencybiasariseswhenthe“catch”isapurelyprivategood,whereasideologicalbiasariseswhentheusershavedifferentpreferenceintensitiesovera “sharedcatch.”

(6)

secondperiodpayoff,maynonethelesshavesignalingvalueforthedecisionmakers.Inotherwords,sinceaffectsDM1’s preferencesoverhischoiceofa1,itisclearthataPolicyAuditcanrevealinformationabout.

Ofcourse,ifSVismuchmorecostlythanPA,thenitisnotaviableoption.TocapturetheideathatSVisonlymarginally morecostlythanSV,weassumethatPolicyAuditsarecostlesswhileStateVerificationcarriesalexicographiccost.9The

assumptionofzerocostforPAiswithoutlossofgeneralityasitpertainstoourmainresult.Specifically,themainresulthere refersthesurprisingoutcomethatDM2maycommittodisclosureandthusforegoPAandSV.AddingacosttoPAtherefore onlyreinforcesthisresult.Moreover,ifthePAcostissufficientlysmall,allourresultsgothrough.10

Thetimingisdepictedschematicallybelow.

3.3. Equilibrium

Weleta1=˛1(,)denotethechoiceofpolicybyDM1givenhisobservationofandDM2’schoiceof.Similarly,we

letm=(,)denoteDM1’schoiceofmessagem.Wealsodenotebyz(,d)theactualobservedoutcomecorrespondingto thetransmissionchoicesanddbyDM2.Accordingtothemodel,z(1,d)=mforalld(i.e.,DM2choosestocommittoview onlymessages),z(0,d)=mwhend=NA,z(0,d)=whend=SV,andz(0,d)=a1whend=PA.Finally,leta2=˛2(z(,d))denote

DM2’schoiceofpolicygivenherobservationz(,d).

WeevaluatekeypropertiesofthePerfectBayesianEquilibria(PBE)ofthegame.FornowwerestrictattentiontoPBEin purestrategies,definedformallybelow.Asidefromthesimplificationthisaffords,weshowinSection5thatmixedstrategy PBEarenon-genericinthebiasparameterb.Moreoverinthose(non-generic)caseswheremixedPBEmayexist,onecan constructapurestrategyPBEthatispayoffequivalentforDM2.

Inthedefinitionbelow,wewillrefertoaPBEissimplyan“equilibrium.”

Definition1. Equilibrium:Anequilibriumisa5-tuple(˛1,,,d,˛2)suchthat

(1)DM1choosesthepair(˛1,)optimallygivenherobservationofandandDM2’s(correctlyanticipated)choiceofd

and˛2.

(2)DM2choosesthetriple(,d,˛2)optimally.Inparticular,anddarechosengivenherbeliefsaboutandhercorrect

anticipationofDM1’schoiceof˛1and.DM2’schoiceof˛2issimilarlyoptimal,reflectingherupdatedbeliefsafter

observingz(,d).

(3)DM2’supdatedbeliefssatisfyBayes’Rulewhereverpossible.

Wefirstestablishabaselinepartialcharacterizationofequilibriathatwillbehelpfulforsubsequentresults.

Proposition1. Fullrevelationwithoutcommitment:Consideranyequilibriumineithertheideologicalortheagencybiasmodel. SupposethatintheequilibriumDM2chooses=0.Thatis,DM2doesnotcommittoobservingonlymessagemandinsteadretains theoptiontoconductapolicyauditorverifythestateatalaterstage.Then

(i)DM1’schoiceofa1=˛1(0,)isfullyrevealingofthestate.

(ii)DM1’smessagestrategy(0,·)inthecontinuationgamefollowing=0coincideswithsomePBEstrategyintheCScheap talkgame.

(iii)DM2choosesapolicyauditsothatd=PAandz(0,PA)=˛1(0,).

(iv)DM2choosesheroptimalsecondperiodactiona2=˛2(z(0,PA))=˛2(˛1(0,))=.

OnesignificantimplicationofProposition1isthatinaworldwherethecommitmenttoforgopolicyauditingandstate verificationisnotpossible,theuninformedagentwouldalwayschoosetoundertakeapolicyaudit.Shewouldneverrelyon messagesalone,andshewouldneverchoosetoverifythestatedirectly.

Intheinterestofbrevity,weomitafullformalproofforProposition1.Theargumentisstandardandwhatfollowsisa sketchofthestepsinvolved.

9 Thatis,PAiscostlesstoimplementbyDM2,andDM2choosesSVifandonlyifthepayoffafterobservingthestateisstrictlylargerthanthepayoffafter observingDM1’saction.

(7)

Assumethatinsomeequilibrium,=0.WhenDM2choosesditisnotpossiblethatshewillsetd=NAandonlyobserve m.Inthiscase,giventhata1issunk,themodelwouldboildowntoaversionoftheCSworld,andthemessagewouldnotbe

fullyrevealingofthestate.HenceDM2coulddeviatetosettingd=SV,observe,andhenceattainahigherpayoff.

CoulditthenbethatDM2setsd=SVinequilibrium?InthiscaseDM1wouldanticipatethathischoiceofa1playsno

(informational)roleinDM2’schoiceofa2.HenceDM1wouldsimplychooseanactionthatmaximizeshis=1payoff,and

hencehischoiceofa1wouldbefullyrevealingofthestate.ButsincebothSVandPAwouldinducefullyrevealingactionsby

DM1andarethusequallyinformative,thepolicyauditPAispreferabletoDM2asthecheaperoption.Hence,DM2would thendeviatetochoosingPA.

ThisinturnmeansthatonlypossibilityisthatDM2choosesPAwhengiventhechance.Coulditbethatthisisthecase andDM1’schoiceofa1isnotfullyrevealingof?Ifthiswerethecase,giventhatlexicographiccostofchoosingSV,DM2

wouldthengainbydeviatingtochoosingSV.Thiswouldgivehermoreinformationandhenceallowhertoimproveher payoff.Hence,weconcludethatinanyequilibriumif=0ischosenthend=PAisalsochosenbyDM2,andfurthermorethat thechoiceofa1onDM1’spartmustbefullyrevealingofthestate.

FromProposition1,theonlycandidatesforequilibriumareeitherforDM2toeitherrelyonthe“words”(thecaseof=1) orthe“actions”(thecaseof=0andd=PA)ofDM1.NoticethatwhileSVwillneverbechoseninequilibrium,itsavailability iscrucialtotheargument.Withoutit,d=NAcouldbechosenbyDM2and,consequently,thepolicyofDM1neednotbefully revealing.

4. Whendoactionsspeaklouderthanwords?

4.1. Ideologicalbias

Webeginwiththecaseofideologicalbias.InthiscaseDM1andDM2differintheirobjectivesinthesamewayacrossthe twoperiods.ForanygivenDM1’sidealpolicyislargerthanthatofDM2.Asweremarkedbefore,thistypeofmisalignment onpreferencesisastylizedrepresentationofpoliticalcompetitionbetweentwopartiesthatholdpowerinsequencebut haveapre-setdifferenceofopinionregardingthedesirablevaluesofagivenpolicyvariable.

FromProposition1weknowthatinthecontinuationofthegamefollowing=0(nocommitment),DM2choosesd=PA andDM1’schoiceofa1mustbefullyrevealingofthestate.Giventhatincheaptalkmodelswithacontinuumofstates(à

laCS)fullyinformativeequilibriaaregenerallyruledout,thepicturethatemergesfromProposition1seemstosaythatin equilibriumweshouldnotobserveDM2actuallycommittoonlyobservingthecheaptalkmessagem.

Yet,thisintuitionturnsouttobefalseinarobustsetofenvironments.ThemainresulttellsusthatwithIdeologicalBias andfor“largeenough”valuesofb,everyequilibriumwillhavethepropertythatDM2commitstoobservethemessages. ThegistoftheargumentreliesonfindingupperandlowerboundsforDM2’spayofffollowingachoiceof=0and=1 respectively.Thisisthereasonwefirststateapreliminarycharacterizationofequilibria,whichsharpenstheconclusionof

Proposition1inthecaseofIdeologicalBias.

Proposition2. Linearpareto-dominantequilibrium:ConsidertheIdeologicalBiascase.IfthereisanyequilibriuminwhichDM2 chooses=0,thenthereisanequilibriumasfollows.

(i)DM2chooses=0.

(ii)DM1’schoiceofpolicyisgivenby˛1(0,)=+2b.

(iii) ThepayoffsassociatedwiththisequilibriumPareto-dominatethoseofallotherequilibriainwhichDM2chooses=0. Forlackofabetterterm,wewillrefertotheequilibriumdescribedinthePropositionasthelinearequilibriumunder IdeologicalBias.Wearenowreadytostateourfirstmainresult.

Proposition3. Sometimeswordsdospeaklouderthanactions:ConsidertheIdeologicalBiascase.Thenthereexistsa ¯b>0such that

(i)Ifb> ¯b,theninanyequilibriumDM2selects=1.Inotherwords,inallequilibriaDM2commitstoobservingmonlyand forgoestheoptiontoconductapolicyauditortoverifythestateatalaterstage.

(ii)Ifb≤ ¯b,thenthereexistsanequilibriuminwhichDM2selects=0,subsequentlychoosestoauditDM1’spolicy(selectsd=PA) andDM1playsaccordingtothelinearequilibriumofProposition2,thussettinga1=˛1(0,)=+2b.

Obviously,thestrongerandmoresurprisingclaiminProposition3ispartiwhichappliestoeveryequilibriumofthe gamewhenb> ¯b.Thus,withalargeenoughideologicalbiasDM2commitstoobserveonlym.Wordsspeaklouderthan actions.

Weemphasizethatthecommitmentoptiontoforegoadiscretionaryauditappearsinmanyenvironments,including nationalsecurityissuesandstandardcorporatepractices.ThePropositionprovidesonerationaleforwhytheoptionwillbe exercised.WelatershowthattheresultholdsupevenifthecommitmentbyDM2requiredtheconsentofDM1.Forbias largeenough,bothpartieswouldprefertoavoidtheaudit(seeSection5).

(8)

ThefullProposition3isinAppendix.Tounderstandtheresult,however,wefinditusefultofirstdeveloptheintuition forparti.Later,wecommentonpartii.

Sinceweareinthecaseofideologicalbias,foranygivenlevelof,DM1’sidealactionsare+bbothinperiod=1and =2.TheseconddecisionmakerDM2favorsactionsequaltoinbothperiods.

Asthe“receiver”ofinformation,DM2choosestoset=1ifbislargeenough.Insodoing,DM2commitstoobserve messagemonly.NotethatDM2losesvaluableinformationsince,justasinCS,misnotfullyinformativeof.Infactthe degreeofinformativenessofmdecreasesasthesizeofbincreases.

AftertheDM2chooses=1,DM1effectivelychoosesa1 “insecret.”HenceDM1willsimplyseta1=+b.Therefore,

regardlessofthefirstperiodpayoffofDM2is−b2(see(1)).DM2thenchoosesa

2afterobservingm,andhence(using(1)

again)hersecondperiodexpectedpayoffcontingentonmis−Var(|m).11

IfDM2weretoset=0instead,weknowfromProposition1thatitwillsubsequentlychoosetosetd=PA,andhence observea1directly.Thekeytoseeingthat,forlargeenoughb,thiswillbeworsethansetting=1,istonotethatafterDM2

sets=0,DM1knowsthata1willbeauditedbyDM2inthesecondperiod(againweobservethefactthatSVisavailable

anddominatesNAiscriticaltothisargument,eventhoughSVisneverchoseninequilibrium).ByProposition1,DM2will havefullinformationaboutonceitobservesa1.ThereforeDM2setsa2=,andthisgivesDM2asecondperiodpayoffof0.

KnowingthatDM2willusetheinformationyieldedbythePolicyAudittoseta2=willinduceDM1to“over-compensate”

duetothemarginaleffectofitsfirstperiodactiononDM2’saction.DM1thereforesetsavalueofa1thatisabove+b.In

fact,weknowfromProposition2thatinthebestcaseforDM2(and,forthatmatter,forDM1aswell),a1willbesettoequal

+2b.Hencethefirst-periodpayofftoDM2isnowworsethantheonewecalculatedfollowing=1sinceitis−4b2.12Since,

aswenotedabove,thesecondperiodpayofftoDM2iszero,thismeansthatitsoverallexpectedpayoffaftersetting=0is atbest−4b2.

Tosumup,DM2’sexpectedpayoffaftersetting=1isboundedbelowby−b2Var(),whileaftersetting=0itis

boundedaboveby−4b2.Sincethedistributionofisgiven,itisthenclearthatwhenbissufficientlylargeDM2mustprefer

toset=1andthusforgoanyPolicyAuditorStateVerificationandrelyonlyonthecheaptalkmessagemsentbyofDM1. Wordsdospeaklouderthanactionsinthiscase.Infact,itisnothardtoextendtheargumentusedtoproveProposition3to showthatifbissufficientlylarge,thenDM2’scommitmenttoobserveonlymisbeneficialtobothplayers.

ThestatementinPart(ii)ofProposition3isnotassharpasonewouldideallylikebecauseoftheunderlyingmultiplicity ofcontinuationequilibriafollowingboth=0and=1inthecasewherebissmall.

TheequilibriumidentifiedinPart(ii)ofProposition3issupported(seeAppendixforthedetailsoftheargument)by choosingababblingequilibriumcontinuationfollowinga choiceof=1andthelinear(Pareto-dominant)equilibrium identifiedinProposition2followingachoiceof=0.

InthemodelweanalyzeitisDM2whochooseswhetherthegamecontinueswithanoptiontoperformPolicyAudit orStateVerificationortoshutdowntheseoptionsandcommittoobservingmonly.Itisthereforelegitimatetoaskwhat happensif,inthespiritofforwardinductionarguments,13werestrictattentionto“continuationequilibria”thatgivethe

bestpossiblepayofftoDM2bothafterachoiceof=0andafterachoiceof=1(thelatterisnotababblingequilibrium).

Definition2. Forwardinductionproofequilibrium:Consideranequilibrium ofthegeneralgame.We defineaforward inductionproofequilibrium(henceforthaFIPE)asaPBEsuchthatthereisnootherPBEwhichyieldsalargercontinuation payofftoDM2followingeitherofitscommitmentactions,either=0or=1.

Inotherwords,aPBEisaFIPEifitmaximizes,amongallPBE’s,DM2’scontinuationpayofffollowinghercommitment decision.Inthespiritofforwardinduction,DM2indicatesherintentionsaboutwhichactionshe’lltakefromherinitial commitmentdecision.Off-pathbeliefsofDM1acceptstheseintentionsandactsaccordingly.

Beforestatingtheresult,werequireonemoreassumption.

Assumption1. Constantdensity:Thestrictlypositivecontinuousdensityffromwhichisdrawnisconstantonsome non-degenerateinterval[, ¯].

Proposition4. ConsidertheIdeologicalBiascaseandletAssumption1hold.Thenthereexistsab>0suchthatforanyb≤b themodelhasauniqueFIPEinwhichDM2sets=0,andsubsequentlychoosesd=PA.

Clearly,b< ¯bwhere ¯bistheboundinProposition3.So,withtherefinementandasmallenoughideologicalbias,apolicy auditmustoccur.Combiningthisresultwithpart(i)ofthepreviousproposition,weobtainasharpcharacterizationofthe chosenvehicleforinformationtransmissionwhenideologicalbiasiseithersufficientlylargeorsufficientlysmall.

11 TheactualvalueofVar(|m)dependsontheentiremessagefunction(·|0)chosenbyDM1inequilibrium. 12 SinceweknowfromProposition1thata

1isfullyrevealingofthestate,wecanwritetheincentive-compatibilityconstraintforDM1asbalancingthe marginal“tangible”payofffroma1(asitentersdirectlyDM1’sfirstperiodpayoff)anditsmarginaleffectonthebeliefsofDM2aboutandhenceona2. Thisgivesrisetoasimpledifferentialequation(see(.5)inAppendix)whichunderpinsthelinearequilibriumofProposition2.

13 Forreasonsofspaceandeaseofreading,westayclearofdetailsabouthowexistingforwardinductionrefinementsspecificallyapplytoourmodel. Instead,werefertheinterestedreadertothecontributionsbyvanDamme(1989),andmorerecentlybyGovindanandWilson(2009),andMan(2012).

(9)

4.2. Agencybias

Ourmodelbehavesquitedifferentlywhenthemis-alignmentinpreferencesbetweenDM1andDM2takestheformof AgencyBias.Recall(see(3))thatinthiscaseDM1favorsahigherlevelofa1thanDM2does,andsimilarly,DM2favorsa

higherlevelofa2thanDM1does.Themanagerwhoisactiveinanyperiod,foranygiven(theexternalmarketfactors

affectingthefirm),favorsahigherlevelofmanagerialperksthanintheperiodinwhichsheisnottheactivemanagerbut holds,say,stockinthefirm.

JustasinthecaseofIdeologicalBias,fromProposition1weknowthatonlytwoalternativesareviableinequilibrium. EitherDM2choosestocommittoobservingonlymandthusforgoesanypossibilitytoauditDM1’spolicyortoverifythestate (DM2sets=1),orshedoesnotcommitinsuchaway(DM2sets=0)andsubsequentlychoosestoobservea1(d=PA).

Recallalsothat,justasinthecaseofIdeologicalBias,Proposition1furthercharacterizesthissecondpossibilitytellingus thatinthiscaseDM1’schoiceofa1mustbefullyrevealingofthestate.

WefirststateourmainresultforthecaseofAgencyBiasandthenelaborateonitsmeaningandtheintuitionbehindit.

Proposition5. Underagencybiasactionsspeaklouderthanwords:ConsiderthecaseofAgencyBias.Then,foranylevelofb, thereisauniqueForwardInduction-Proofequilibrium(FIPE)inwhich

(i)DM2chooses=0therebynotcommittingtoobservingmaloneandretainstheoptiontocarryoutaPolicyAuditorState Verification.

(ii)DM2choosesapolicyauditsothatd=PAandz(0,PA))=˛1(0,).

(iii) DM2enjoyshergloballyoptimalpayoffof0.

NotethatcombiningProposition5withProposition1weknowthatintheequilibriumsingledoutbyProposition5,DM2 proceedstosetd=PAandsotoauditDM1’spolicyandobservea1directly,thusgainingfullknowledgeoftheactualvalue

of.

JustasinthecaseofProposition3,theremaybeamultiplicityofPBE.However,FIPErulesoutanycontinuationother thantheoneinwhich(a)thefullyrevealing(linear)equilibriumisplayedfollowingthechoiceof=0,and(b)thebestCS equilibrium(fromDM2’spointofview)isplayedfollowingthechoiceof=1.Facedwiththesetwocontinuations,DM2 willchoose=0intheagencybiasmodel.

Theintuitionfortheresultcanbeunderstoodbyjuxtaposingtheagencybiasmodelwiththeideologicalbiasmodel.In bothmodels,theactionofthefirstdecisionmaker,DM1,playstworoles.Firstly,ithas“tangible”valueforbothDM1and DM2sinceitentersdirectlytheirpayoffs.Secondly,ithasasignalingrolesinceitpotentiallyrevealstheactualvalueofto DM2–infact,byProposition1,itactuallydoesrevealitinanyequilibriuminwhich=0.Inbothmodels,themarginaleffect (viasignaling)ofDM1’sactiononDM2’sactionwillbeweightedbyDM1togetherwiththetangiblevalueofheractionasit entersherfirstperiodpayoff.

Unliketheideologicalbiasmodel,underagencybiasDM1wouldliketodistortDM2’sactiondownwardratherthan upward.Inordertodothisviasignaling,hisownactionshouldbelessdistortedthanwouldbeoptimalfromapurely tangiblepayoffpointofview.Thatistosay,thesignalingvalueofDM1’sactionworksinoppositiontoitstangiblevalue. Thisisquitedifferentthantheideologicalbiascasewheretangiblevalueandsignalingvaluearereinforcing–bothmotivate DM1todistorthisactionupward.

UnderagencybiasthetwoopposingforceseffectivelycanceloutmakingDM1’schoiceequaltotheonethatisthe overallfavoriteofDM2,namelya1=.14HenceDM2endsupenjoyingheroveralloptimalpayoffunderaPolicyAuditthatis

anticipatedbyDM1.Henceshechoosesnottocommittoobservingmonlywhengiventhechance.Actionsdoindeedspeak louderthanwordsintheAgencyBiascase.

5. Robustness

Anumberofextensionsor“robustnesschecks”areworthdiscussing.Weintroducewhatwebelievearethemostcritical onesandanalyzeeachinturn.

Mixedstrategies.Theanalysisthusfarfocussedexclusivelyonpurestrategies.Wegiveabriefargumentdemonstrating themainresultsextendtothemixedstrategycase,althoughwedonotgiveaprecisecharacterizationofallmixedequilibria ofthemodel.

ConsiderfirstProposition1,theprecursortosubsequentresults.SupposeweareatthestageinwhichDM2didnotalready committodisclosureandmustnowchoosebetweenPA(auditing),NA(messages),andSV(stateverification)followingDM1’s choices.

IsthereanequilibriuminwhichDM2mixesatthisstage?NoticeattheoutsetthatDM2mustassignzeroprobabilityto NA.IfDM2assignspositiveprobabilitytoNA,thenDM1’smessageisnotfullyinformative(asshowninCS).Inthatcase, DM2strictlyprefersSVtoNAsincetheverificationcostissmallerthanitsbenefits.NoticealsothatDM2willnotrandomize

14ThedifferentialequationembodyingDM1’sIncentiveCompatibilityconstraint(see(.17)inAppendix)nowyieldsa

(10)

betweenPAandSV.IfDM1’sactionisfullyrevealing,thenDM2strictlyprefersPA.Iftheactionisnotfullyrevealingthen DM2strictlyprefersSV.Hence,inequilibriumDM2choosesPA.

WillDM2actuallybewillingtorandomizeatthecommitmentstage?Infact,thiscanhappenonlyifDM2isindifferent betweenPAandNA.Intheideologicalbiascasewithblarge,babblingisstrictlybetterforhimthanthefullyrevealing continuation.15Similarly,witheitheragencybias,orideologicalbiaswithbsmall,thefullyrevealingcontinuationisstrictly

betterthananyother.

Inshort,indifferencebyDM2isnon-generic.Moreover,iftheredoesexistanequilibriuminwhichDM2mixes,thereis apurestrategyequilibriumthatispayoffequivalent.

Auditingcosts.Themodelassumesthatauditingcostsarezero.Considerwhathappenswhenweallowforpositive auditingcostsinthemodel.Theresultsholdupifauditingcostsareintroduced,providedtheyaresmallenough.Thekey observationisthat,aslongasstateverificationismarginallycostlierthanthepolicyaudit,thelatterwillalwaysinduce fullyrevealingactionsbyDM1.Inthatcase,thepolicyauditwillalwaysbethebetteroption.Consequently,Proposition1, thegatewaytothesubsequentresults,continuestohold.Moreover,ifthePAcostissmallenough,thenitwillstillbethe preferredoptionoverdisclosureinthosecaseswherePAwaschoseninthemodelwithzeroauditingcosts.16

Noticethatifmixedstrategiesareintroducedinthemodelwithpositiveauditingcosts,theywillbenongenericforthe samereasonsoutlinedabove.Notealsothatif=1ischosenunderzeroPAcosts,thenitwillbechosenwhensuchcosts arepositive.Themoresubtlecaseiswhen=0andd=PA.SincethefullyrevealingcontinuationunderPAisstrictlybetter thananyotherwhenauditingcostsarezero,itwillbesowhencostsarelowenoughtopreservethestrictinequality.17

Discounting.Inadynamicmodel,itisnaturaltoaskwhathappensiftheplayersdiscountthefuture,sothatinourcase thesecondperiodpayoffsothatitismultipliedbyafactorı∈(0,1).Thegistofourresultssurvivesintactthediscounting ofsecondperiodpayoffsbyDM1andDM2.

Propositions2and3continuetoholdwiththeonlyamendmentthatthelinearequilibriumisnow˛1(0,)=+(1+ı)b.

Thethresholds ¯b andb< ¯b needtoberecalculatedforthediscountingcase,buttheirexistenceremainsexactlyasstatedin

Propositions3and4.Proposition5partialsocontinuestohold.

InshorttheoverallpictureframedbyPropositions3–5continuestoholdwhendiscountingisallowed.Wordsspeak louderthanactionsinthecaseofIdeologicalBiasandblarge,whileactionsspeaklouderthanwordswhenbissmalland weareintheIdeologicalBiascase,orforanyvalueofbwhenweareinthecaseofAgencyBias.

Theabilitytocommit.Weremarkedearlierthatcommitmentstoforegoauditsarecommonpracticeinfirms.Toa morelimitedextent,theyalsoexistinpolities–particularlyinareasofnationalsecurity.Onecouldtakeissuewiththefact that,unlikeourmodelwhereDM2makesthecommitment,thesecommitmentsareinstitutionalinnature.Theyareoften agreeduponeitherbynon-partisancommittees(e.g.,thefirm’sBoardofDirectors),orunanimousagreementbytheparties themselves.Ourresultscanbeextendedtoaccommodatethispossibility.

ConsideranextrastepinthemodelwherebyaproposedcommitmenttoforegoauditingbyDM2requirestheapproval ofDM1–aParetocriterionofsortsthatdetermineswhetherthecommitmenttousedisclosureistaken.Nowconsider twoinstitutions(formally,twodistinctgames).Inonegame,theonewe’veanalyzedsofar,thereexistsadecisionnodein whichDM2cancommittousedisclosure.Intheothergame,nosuchcommitmentoptionisavailable.Thatis,withoutthe commitmentoption,DM2mustsimultaneouslychoosebetweenallthreeoptions-disclosure,auditing,directverification afterDM1’saction.

Intheideologybiasmodelwiththecommitmentoption,whenbiasbislarge,Proposition3showsthatDM2prefers tocommittodisclosure.ButthisisalsotrueforDM1.Inotherwords,forblargebothdecisionmakersprefertomakethe commitment.Toseewhy,observethatunderauditing,DM1’stotalpayoffis−2b2.Underdisclosure,theworstcanhappento

DM1isbabblingandDM1’slowerboundinthiscaseis−Var()−b2.Thusforblarge,disclosurethecommitmenttoavoid

auditing–Paretodominatestheoptiontoaudit.Inthissense,thetwoagentspreferaninstitutioninwhichacommitment optionexiststoavoiddiscretionaryaudits.

Bycontrast,whenbissmall,thenbothpartiespreferauditing.Inthiscasethepresenceorabsenceofthecommitment optioninthemodeldoesnotaffecttheoutcome.Thepartiesarethereforeindifferentaboutwhichofthetwogames,i.e., whichinstitutionalenvironment,theyarein.

Nowconsidertheagencybiasmodelwiththecommitmentoption.Here,whenthebiasbissmall,thenbothpartieswould preferauditing.AgainthereisaclearParetorankingbutthepresenceorabsenceofthecommitmentoptioninthemodel doesnotaffecttheoutcome.Thepartiesareonceagainindifferentaboutwhichofthetwogames,i.e.,whichinstitutional environment,theyarein.

Forthesakeofcompleteness,weobservethatwhenbislargeintheagencybiasmodel,DM2andDM1haveopposing preferencesonthecommitmentdecision.ByProposition4,thedecisioninthehandsofDM2resultsinauditing.18

15 WeemphasizethatDM1’schoicedependsontheoutcomeofDM2’smixedstrategy,notonthemixedstrategyitself.Forthisreason,DM1doesnotmix, andsoneitherdoesDM2exceptonanongenericsetofb.

16 Roughly,wecanboundthepayoffofthemostinformativecheaptalkequilibriumoftheCScheaptalkgame.SincetheactionbyDM1inthePA continuationisfullyrevealing,itwillbestrictlypreferrediftheauditingcostisverysmall.

17 TheremayofcoursebeanauditingcosttocreateanindifferencebetweenPAandNA,butthiscasewouldbenon-generic.

(11)

Hence,exceptforthislastcase,bothplayerswouldprefer,atleastweakly,tobeinaninstitution(agame)inwhichthe commitmentoption–theoptiontoforegodiscretionaryauditing–isavailable.

Quadraticlosspayoffs.Throughout,wehaveworkedwithpreferencesrepresentedbytime-separablequadratic-loss functions.SinceCS,quadraticpreferenceshavebeenthecanonicalbenchmarkcasethroughouttheliteratureon cheap-talk.Acrossthisfield,quadraticpreferencesalsohavetheprivilegedpositionofguaranteeingtractability,yieldingexplicit solutionsinmanycases.Theyplayessentiallythesameroleinourmodel.

Itislegitimatetoaskhowcrucialtheirroleisinthequalitativeflavoroftheresultsweobtainhere.Wedonotdemonstrate ageneralresultinthepaper,however,thenatureoftheresultsindicatethatthesepreferencesarenot“knife-edged.”

AsimplewaytoseethisistoobservethatDM2’stransmissionchoicesarediscreteandgenericallyherbestresponsesin equilibriumarestrict.Thismeansthattheargumentsshouldgothroughunchangedinawelldefinedcontinuousparametric neighborhoodofthequadraticpreferences.Totakeoneexample,supposeWi=Vi+(1−)UiwhereViisthequadraticpayoff

specifiedbeforeandUiisasmoothfunctionofactions,stateandbiasandstrictlyconcaveintheaction.Fortheresultto

extend,onewouldshowthattheresultsremainintactforWiifiscloseenoughtoone.19Westronglyconjecturethisis

thecase,butdonotproveitformally.

6. Auditsandpartisaninvestigations

Thispaperhasemphasizedtheimportanceofendogenouschoiceoftransmissionprotocolindecentralizeddecisions problems.Therearemanysuchproblemsinwhichtheinterestsofrelevantdecisionmakersdonotcoincide.Wefocuson twocleavages–ideologicalandagency–thatdifferentiateauthorityfiguresatdifferentdecisiondates.

Theresultssuggestthatthecommitmenttoasystemofdisclosureismorevaluablewhenthecleavagebetweendecision makersisideological.Wearguedthat,broadlyspeaking,theIdeologicalBiascasefitsbetterthepoliticaleconomyscenarioin whichtwopartiessuccessivelyholdpower,whiletheagencycaseisarguablybettersuitedtorepresentprivateorganizations inwhichtwodecisionmakersarechoseninternallytoheadtheoperationsinsuccession.20

This,inourview,talliessignificantlywiththefactthatAuditingdoesinfactprevailinthecaseoffirms.Audits(internal andexternal)arealmostalwaysthoughtofas“goodmanagementpractices”inthecaseofthefirms,21whereasauditsinthe

politicalsphereareoftenviewedas“partisanwitchhunts.”Whenanewpoliticalpartyoccupiespowerithaswidepowers torenegeonpreviouspromises,ifnecessarybychangingthelaw.Onenotableexceptionisintheareaofnationalsecurity. Institutionalcommitmentstoavoidpublicauditsofsensitivesecurityexistandareusuallyagreeduponbyallparties.

Itisworthemphasizingthatdecisionproblemsofthisnaturealsoariseinmoreamorphoussettings.22Whetherthe

institutionisformalorinformal,wepointoutthatiflegal/institutionalcommitmentsarefeasible,thenbothdecisionmakers atleastweaklyprefertheminallcases,agencyorideologicalbias,largeorsmallb,exceptunderagencybiaswhenbislarge. Finally,theresultsindicatethatwhensuchcommitmentisnotpossibletheoutcomewillinfactbeanAuditoftheactions ofthepreviouspartybythenewholderofpower.Atthispointthelossofwelfarerelativetothedisclosureregimemaywell becomeapparenttotheparticipants,butitsimplyistoolatetoavoidit.Afutureexplorationintowhen,how,andwhysuch commitmentsarepossibleinsomeenvironmentsandnotinotherswouldbewellworththeeffort.

Appendix.

ProofofofProposition2. Consider theIdeologicalBiascase,andassumethatthereisanequilibriumwith=0.By

Proposition1thenthereisanequilibriumwith=0,d=PAand˛1(0,)fullyrevealingof.Letthisequilibriumbedenoted

by(˛∗1,∗,∗,d∗,˛∗2).Foreveryvalueof,DM1’spolicychoicea1=˛∗1(0,)mustsolve

max

a1

−(a1−−b)2−[˛∗2(a1)−−b]2

Assuming˛∗2isdifferentiable,23wecanwritethefirstorderconditionas

˛∗1(0,)−−b+[˛∗2(˛∗1(0,))−−b]˛∗2(˛∗1(0,))=0

Since˛∗1(0,)isfullyrevealingandDM2’soptimala2isequaltoforanygiven,wemusthavethat˛∗2[˛∗1(0,)]=

˛∗1 −1[˛∗1(0,)]=.FromtheInverseFunctionTheorem,wethenknowthat˛∗2[˛∗1(0,)]=1/˛∗1(0,).

19Theexactcutoffsinbwouldobviouslybedifferent.

20Theserepresentationsare,ofcourse,approximate.Forinstance,office-motivatedpoliticiansasopposedtotheideology-drivenoneswehaveinmind here–mayfitbetterthecaseofAgencyBias.

21SeeArter(2000). 22Seefootnote8.

23Forthisstepoftheargumentofcourseitissufficienttoverifyex-postthatfunctionwefindisindeeddifferentiable.Intheproofofpartiii)belowthis isnotaviableoption.However,sinceweknowfromProposition1thatwearedealingwithfullyrevealingequilibriaitiseasytoseethatDM1’sdecision mustbecontinuousandstrictlymonotoneinandhencedifferentiablealmosteverywhere.Thisissufficientforourpurposesbelow,thoughthedetails areomittedforthesakeofbrevity.

(12)

Hence,thefirstorderconditionimpliesthatthefollowingdifferentialequationmustbesatisfied

[˛∗1(0,)−−b]˛∗1(0,)−b=0 (.5)

Noticethat˛∗1(0,)=+2bisonesolutiontothisdifferentialequation(and,pointbypoint,satisfiestherequiredsecond ordercondition).

ThissufficestoprovepartiiofProposition2.Forfuturereference,atthispointwenoticethat˛∗1(0,)=+2banda2=

foreveryimplyanequilibriumpayoffforDM2of−4b2.

ToshowpartsiandiiiofProposition2,usingpartiofProposition1,itissufficienttoshowthatthepayoffsassociatedwith thelinearequilibriuminwhich=0and˛∗1(0,)=+2bPareto-dominatethoseofanyotherfullyrevealingequilibrium inwhichDM2sets=0.

Consideragainthedifferentialequationin(.5),whichweknowanyfullyrevealingequilibriumtobeconsideredhere mustsatisfy(almosteverywhere).

Define

g







=˛1(0,)−−b (.6)

andnotice

g()=˛∗1(0,)−1 (.7)

Hence,wecanrewrite(.5)as

g





 

1+g







=b (.8)

Theng*()=bisonesolutionto(.8),givingrisetothelinearequilibriumstrategy˛

1(0,)=+2bthatweidentifiedabove.

In general, however, there are infinitely many solutions to (.8), corresponding to infinitely many fully revealing equilibria.24

Oncewehaveagthatsolves(.8),foranygiventhepayoffstothedecisionmakersinthecorrespondingequilibrium, canberespectivelywrittenas

V1=−g()2−b2 and V2=−[b+g()]2

Moreover,observethat,wheneverg()>0,bothpayoffsaredecreasinging().

Therestoftheproofconsistsofshowingthatifgisasolutiontothedifferentialequationin(.8)andg /= g*,theng()b

forevery.Thiswillsufficetoshowthatinanyotherequilibriumtobeconsideredthepayoffstobothdecisionmakersare lowerthanthoseonthelinearequilibrium,asrequired.

Consideragainthedifferentialequationin(.8).Beginbynotingthatdirectlyfromthedifferentialequationitselfweknow thatitisimpossiblethatg()=0forany.Hence,sincegiscontinuousanddifferentiablealmosteverywhere,ifg(ˆ)is positive(negative)forsome ˆtheng()mustbepositive(negative)forall ∈R.

Now,bywayofcontradiction,considerasolution ˜g to(.8)suchthatforsome ˆ wehave ˜g(ˆ)<b.Weneedtodistinguish betweentwocases–first ˜g(ˆ)>0,andthen ˜g(ˆ)<0.

Considerthecaseof ˜g(ˆ)>0first.Sincebyourcontradictionhypothesis ˜g(ˆ)<b,directlyfrom(.8)wegetthat ˜g()< ˜g()<bforallpairs{,}satisfying<and< ˆ.

Restrictingattentiontoanappropriatesubsequenceifnecessary,wethenhavethat lim

→−∞˜g

()=0.Since ˜g()<bforall

< ˆ,thisimpliesthatforsomesufficientlysmall ¯ itmustbethat

˜g( ¯)[1+ ˜g( ¯)]<b (.9)

whichdirectlyimpliesthat ˜gcannotbeasolutionto(.8).

Wenowturntothesecondcase–so,assume ˜g(ˆ)<0.Similarlytowhatwearguedinthepreviouscase,thisimplies that ˜g()< ˜g()<0forallpairs{,}satisfying<and< ˆ.

Justasinthepreviouscase,andagainrestrictingattentiontoanappropriatesubsequenceifnecessary,wethenhavethat lim

→−∞˜g

()=0.Since ˜g()<0forall< ˆ,thisimpliesthatforsomesufficientlysmall ¯itmustbethat

˜g( ¯)[1+ ˜g( ¯)]0 (.10)

whichdirectlyimpliesthat ˜g cannotbeasolutionto(.8).

24 Anothersolutionis,forexample, ˆg()=b[W (e1−/b)+1]whereWistheso-calledLambertWfunctionwhichisimplicitlydefinedby=W







eW(). Thefunction ˆgsatisfies ˆg (0)=2b(whichcanbeinterpretedastheinitialcondition).Thefunction ˆgthereforegivesrisetoanotherfullyrevealingequilibrium inwhichtheinformedDM’spolicyis˛ˆ1(,0)= ˆg()++b.Itisalsoeasytocheckthatthereareinfinitelymanyothersolutionsgtothedifferentialequation in(.8).Suppose ¯gisasolutionto(.8).Fixanddefine ˜gbyletting ˜g()= ¯g(+)forevery.Then ˜gisalsoasolution.

(13)

LemmaA.1. ConsiderthecaseofIdeologicalBias.SupposethatDM2sets=1andDM2chooses˛1andoptimally.Thenby

choosinga2(m)=E()foreverym,DM2achievesanoverallexpectedpayoffof−b2−Var().25

Proof. GiventhatDM2chooses=1,DM1’schoiceofa1willnotbeobservedbyDM2.Hence,from(1)itisevidentthatit

isoptimalforDM1toseta1=+bforevery ∈R.HenceDM2’sfirstperiodexecutedpayoffis−b2.Againdirectlyfrom(1),

ignoringmandsettinga2=E(),itisclearthatDM2canachieveasecond-periodexpectedpayoffofVar().

LemmaA.2. ConsiderthecaseofIdeologicalBias.InanyequilibriuminwhichDM2sets=0heroverallexpectedpayoffis boundedaboveby−4b2.

Proof. FromProposition1weknowthatsuchequilibriummustentailachoiceofd=PA,andmustbefullyrevealing.Hence DM2willbeabletoinferfromobservinga1.Therefore,from(1),DM2willchoosea2=forevery,andhenceachievea

secondperiodexpectedpayoffof0.This,ofcourse,isDM2’sgloballyoptimalexpectedpayoffinthesecondperiod. FromProposition2weknowthatDM2’soverallpayoffcannotbeabovetheonesheobtainsinthelinearequilibriumin whichDM1setsa1=+2bforevery ∈R.ThisgivesDM2afirstperiodexpectedpayoffof−4b2.

ProofofofProposition3. Let ¯b=



Var()/3.Notethatthistriviallyimpliesthatforeveryb> ¯bwemusthavethat −4b2<b2Var(),andforeveryb≤ ¯b wehavethat−4b2b2Var().

Weprovepartifirst.Suppose,bywayofcontradiction,thatb> ¯bandthatthereexistsanequilibriuminwhichDM2 chooses=0.ByLemmaA.2,insuchaputativeequilibriumDM2’spayoffisboundedaboveby−4b2.ByLemmaA.1,by

deviatingandsetting=1,DM2willachieveapayoffthatisboundedbelowby−b2Var().Thisisevidentlyaprofitable

deviationfromtheputativeequilibriumandhencetheproofofpartiisnowcomplete.

Nowfortheproofofpartii.Letanyb≤ ¯b begiven,andconstructanequilibriumasfollows.DM2chooses=0,and followingthischoice,on-path,thelinearequilibriumofProposition2isplayed.IfDM2deviatesandsets=1,ababbling equilibriumisplayedinwhichDM1choosesafixed ¯m regardlessofandDM2choosesa1=E().DM2’spayoffintheproposed

equilibriumis−4b2.Ifinsteadhedeviatesandsets=0hispayoffis−b2Var().Sinceb≤ ¯b thisisnotaprofitabledeviation

andhencetheproofofpartiiisnowcomplete.

PreliminaryresultsfortheproofofProposition4.BeforeproceedingwiththeproofofProposition4,weletϕdenote theprobabilitythat ∈[, ¯]asrequiredbyDefinition1.

DefinitionA.1. Boundedpartitional:Ancontinuationequilibriumofthegamefollowing=1isboundedpartitionalifand onlyifDM1’sstrategypartitionsthesetofpossible(namelyR)intodisjointintervals(overwhichthemessagedoesnot change),andthelengthofsuchintervalsisboundedawayfromzero.

LemmaA.3. Foranyb>0,allcontinuationequilibriaofthegamefollowing=0areboundedpartitional.

Proof. ThisisastraightforwardadaptationofargumentsinCS(tothecaseof ∈Rratherthanaboundedinterval),and thedetailsareomitted.

LemmaA.4. SupposethatAssumption 1holds.Letadecreasingsequenceofstrictlypositivebiasparameters{bk}∞k=0 with

lim

k→∞bk=0begiven.

Consideranysequenceofassociatedcontinuationequilibriaofthegamefollowing=1,andletV2k∗ bethesequenceofassociated payoffsforDM2.

AssumethatthatforeveryktheequilibriumstrategyofDM1partitions[, ¯]intoatmosttwosets(atmosttwodistinct messagesaresentinequilibriumasrangesover[, ¯]).

Then,thereexistsa ¯ksuchthatforeveryk≥ ¯k,wehavethatV2k∗ <−4b2 k.

Proof. Letabbegiven.ConsiderastrategyforDM1thatentailssendingeitheroneortwomessagesasrangesover[, ¯]. Supposeonlyonemessageissent,say ˆm.Conditionalon ∈[, ¯],DM2’spayoffisthenboundedaboveby−Var(| ∈[, ¯]). Supposenextthatonlytwomessagearesent,say ˆm and ˆˆm.ThenthepayofftoDM2isboundedaboveby−Var(| ∈ [, ¯]andm= ˆm)−Var(|∈[, ¯]andm= ˆˆm).Notethattheseboundsdonotdependonb,butonlyonthedistributionof .Letthebestpossibleboundbedenotedby− (with >0).ThenifDM1onlysendsoneortwomessagesasrangesover [, ¯]thesecondperiodpayofftoDM2isboundedaboveby− ϕ.ThisisbecauseDM2’spayoffconditionalon∈/[, ¯]isat most0.Sinceinanycontinuationequilibriumofthegamefollowing=1,DM1obviouslychoosesa1=+b,DM2’spayoff

inanysuchequilibriumis−b2.Hence,wecanconcludethatifDM1onlysendsoneortwomessagesasrangesover[, ¯]

inanycontinuationequilibriumofthegamefollowing=1,theoverallpayofftoDM2isboundedaboveby−b2 ϕ.

Since− ϕ doesnotdependonb,forbsufficientlysmallitisevidentthat −b2 ϕ<−4b2.Theclaimthen follows

immediately.

ProofofofProposition4. Bywayofcontradictionassumethatthereexistsadecreasingsequenceofbiasparameters {bk}∞k=0withklim→∞bk=0,suchthatforeachbkinthesequencethemodelhasaFIPEinwhichDM2actuallychooses=1.

(14)

NoticefirstthatbyPropositions1and2weknowthatinanyFIPEtheplayers’strategiesconditionalon=0giveriseto thelinearequilibriumofProposition2andhenceyieldapayoffofV2k∗ =−4b2

ktoDM2.

ByLemmaA.4,itmustbethat,contingenton=1,foreverykinthesequence(discardtheinitialelementsifnecessary) DM1’sstrategyinvolvessendingatleastthreedifferentmessagesasrangesover[, ¯].

OurnextendeavoristocomputeanupperboundtoDM2’spayoffcontingenton=0–orequivalentlyinthecontinuation equilibriumofthegamefollowing=1.

Foranygivenbk,considerthepartitionofthesetofpossible(namelyR)inducedbyDM1’sstrategy(seeLemmaA.3).

Considertheleft-mostcellofsuchpartitionsuchthatitsupperboundisnosmallerthan.Letsuchboundbedenotedbydk.

Considernexttheright-mostcellofsuchpartitionsuchthatitslowerboundisnolargerthan ¯.Letsuchboundbedenoted by ¯dk.Withoutlossofgenerality(bytakingsubsequencesifnecessary)weassumethatbothsequences{dk}∞k=0and{¯dk}

∞ k=0

convergeask→∞.

Noticenextthatitmustbethecasethat lim

k→∞( ¯dk−dk)=>0 (.11)

Thisissimplybecauseotherwisewecouldobtainacontradictionusingthesameargument(inthelimit)asintheproof ofLemmaA.4.Letkbetheprobabilitythat ∈[dk, ¯dk]and lim

k→∞k=.NotethatbyAssumption1itmustbethat=

ϕ/( ¯−)andhence>0.

Noticethatatthispointweknowthatcontingenton ∈[dk, ¯dk],thecontinuationequilibriumofthegamefollowing

=1isexactlythemodelinCSinthespecialcaseofauniformdensity.26

LetU(dk, ¯dk,b

k)beDM2’ssecondperiodpayoffunderthemostinformative(theonethatgivesDM2thehighestpayoff),

contingenton [dk, ¯dk].Overall,DM2’sequilibriumpayoffinthecontinuationequilibriumofthegamefollowing=1is

thenboundedaboveby −b2

k+kU(dk, ¯dk;bk) (.12)

ThisissimplybecauseDM2’sfirstperiodpayoffinanyequilibriumofthecontinuationequilibriumofthegamefollowing =1is−b2

kandwhenever∈/[dk, ¯dk]DM2’ssecondperiodpayoffobviouslycannotexceed0.

Ourcontradictionhypothesisand(.12)implythatthereexistsn∈Nsuchthatforeveryk≥n, −b2 k+  2U(dk, ¯dk,bk)≥−4b 2 k (.13) whichimplies U(dk, ¯dk;bk)6b 2 k  (.14)

DirectlyfromCSintheconstantdensitycase27wegetthat

U(dk, ¯dk,bk)=−Akb2k−Bk (.15)

forsomepositiveAkandBk.AlsodirectlyfromCS,thereexistsm∈Nsuchthatforeveryk≥mwehavethatAk>6/.Hence,

fork≥max{n,m}itmustbethat U(dk, ¯dk,bk)=−Akb2k−Bk<−

6b2 k

 (.16)

whichcontradictsinequality(.14)andhenceconcludestheproof

WecontinuewithapreliminaryresultthatwillbeusedtoproveProposition5.

LemmaA.5. ConsidertheAgencyBiascase.IfthereisanyequilibriuminwhichDM2chooses=0,thenthereisanequilibrium asfollows.

(i)DM2chooses=0.

(ii)DM1’schoiceofpolicyisgivenby˛1(0,)=.

(iii)ThepayoffsassociatedwiththisequilibriumPareto-dominatethoseofallotherequilibriainwhichDM2chooses=0. WewillrefertothisasthelinearequilibriumunderAgencyBias.

26 CSconsiderexplicitlythecaseofauniformlydistributedover[0,1].Anappropriatescalefactorneedstobefactoredintoconformtothe(sub-)model wehavehere.

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

In Figure 14 we show the results of wide-angle AVA-petrophysical inversion performed in a different CMP location where well control is not available to validate

In realtà il caso di Alba mostra come fosse proprio il nucleo più antico del liber - in questo caso, quello redatto nel 1215 - ad accogliere solo testi diplomatistici,

This is currently investigated using science data cubes and wavefront sensors data (see Sect. 5.4) and will lead to complementary Level 2 data after frame selection, in addition

Le opinioni espresse in ordine alla natura dei delitti qualificati dall'esito, da parte di quella dottrina che ritiene l'evento un elemento costitutivo e non

In the present study, we compare (for intestinal protozoan infections) this new diagnostic approach with the previous routine based on the coproparasitological exam of three

chemical te4tment on rows integrated with hoeings) on respiratory activity, microbial biomass C, metabolic quotient (qCO), organic C content, mineralization

the number of admissions and the number of days of hospitalizations for cardiomyopathies, secondary hypertension and congestive heart failure, the number of coronary heart

To check in Tg mice 1) the effects of OLE or a mix of polyphenol extracts or hydrohytyrosol (HT) on cognitive functions and neuropathology and 2) the effect of