• Non ci sono risultati.

Ethical and legal issues in gestational surrogacy

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Ethical and legal issues in gestational surrogacy"

Copied!
3
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

Open Med. 2018; 13: 119-121

Conference article

Claudia Casella, Emanuele Capasso, Lucia Terracciano*, Paola Delbon, Piergiorgio Fedeli,

Francesco Antonio Salzano, Fabio Policino, Massimo Niola

Ethical and legal issues in gestational surrogacy

https://doi.org/10.1515/med-2018-0019

received January 8, 2018; accepted March 2, 2018

Abstract: This study originated from events that occurred

in 2014 in an Italian hospital, where the embryos of a couple, obtained by means of homologous insemination, were mistakenly implanted into the uterus of another woman who, along with her husband, underwent the same treatment.

Faced with this serious adverse circumstance, that gives rise to ethical and legal issues, the authors conducted a comparative examination of how to consider the divi-sion of maternity (between biological mother and uterine mother) and the related division of paternity (between genetic father and legal father, husband or partner of the gestational mother).

Some preliminary observations are made concerning parenthood and filiation within the context of currently applicable Italian law.

The following is a detailed analysis of the arguments in favour of the parental figures involved (gestational mother/genetic mother).

Keywords: Assisted reproduction; Pregnancy; Embryo;

Gestational surrogacy

1 Introduction

The significance of health, in its most modern and evolved sense, as a general and inviolable expectation in one’s “search for happiness” [1] suggests that any prospect of not being able to fulfil one’s desire to become a parent is unacceptable.

Assisted reproductive techniques have enormously extended the possibilities of “having a child” but at the same time they have further complicated the issues relat-ing to the determination of filiation.

The simplest situation seems to be that of so-called homologous assisted reproduction, where both partners in a couple participate and thus where there is a coexistence of biological, legal and social parenthood. Even in this field, however, controversial issues arise. For example, who can legitimately become a parent in cases where an embryo, obtained in vitro with oocytes and sperm from an identified couple, is implanted by mistake into the uterus of a women who is extraneous to the couple?

2 Discussion

In this regard, at least three cases have been reported in the USA where the outcomes were different. In 1999 there was the case of Richard and Donna Fasano of New York, who had twins, one of which was black, due to a mistak-enly implanted embryo. The biological parents obtained custody of the child, who was thus separated from his brother.

In 2004 an “extended family” was created when a judge ruled on a matter in which a woman from Califor-nia (Susan Buchweitz) had been implanted with embryos from another couple. In this case, besides ordering a one-million-dollar compensation, the magistrate ruled for “joint custody” of the child.

Five years later (2009), Carolyn Savage from Ohio, due to a mistake by the clinic, gave birth to another cou-ple’s son. The couple took the case to the same clinic, and Carolyn decided to return the child to them. “The doctors immediately advised me to have an abortion” said Carolyn,

*Corresponding author: Lucia Terracciano, Department of Advanced

Biomedical Sciences, University of Naples, Section of Legal Medici-ne, Via Sergio Pansini 5, 80131, Naples, Italy, e-mail: luciaterraccia-no13@gmail.com

Claudia Casella, Emanuele Capasso, Fabio Policino, Massimo Niola,

Department of Advanced Biomedical Sciences, Naples, Italy, Univer-sity of Naples “Federico II”. Via Sergio Pansini 5, 80131, Naples, Italy

Paola Delbon, Department of Surgery, Radiology and Public Health,

Public Health and Humanities Section, University of Brescia – Centre of Bioethics Research (with the contribution of IRCCS “S.Giovanni di Dio – Fatebenefratelli”), Italy. P.le Spedali Civili, 1, 25123 Brescia, Italy

Piergiorgio Fedeli, Jurisprudence School, University of Camerino,

Via A. D’Accorso 16, 62032 Camerino (MC), Italy

Francesco Antonio Salzano, Department of Medicine, Surgery and

Dentistry “Salernitan Medical School”, University of Salerno.

Open Access. © 2018 Claudia Casella et al., published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-Non-Commercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. Brought to you by | Sistema Bibliotecario di Ateneo

Authenticated Download Date | 4/19/18 10:09 AM

(2)

120 Claudia Casella et al.

but “what I was carrying in my womb was a human life and we had to protect that. It didn’t matter if that child was in the wrong tummy. It wasn’t our fault or his parents’ fault. I put myself in the shoes of that child’s mother: what would I have done if my son had been in another woman’s tummy? Wouldn’t I have prayed with all my heart for that woman to let my son live?”.

And finally in 2011, in Hong Kong, two “mistaken” embryos were implanted into a woman. The matter was brought to a close with an abortion [2] and payment of compensation [3].

In Italy, however, in the last eighteen years only three cases have reached the pages of the national newspa-pers: two in Turin (2004) and Padua (2009), where on the morning of the implant the doctors realised the mistake and the women decided to have medical abortions. Another case occurred in 2014 at the Sandro Pertini Hos-pital in Rome where, because of a banal human error, two couples who had given their consent to assisted reproduc-tion were assigned the embryos of the other.

These two parallel implants did not have the same outcome: one was not successful, in that the pregnancy did not even initiate; the other led to the successful birth of twins.

The couple, to whom the genetic heritage of the expected twins was traceable, lodged an appeal to the court of Rome.

On this subject, there is an illuminating opinion expressed by the National Bioethics Committee entitled “Bioethical considerations on the involuntary switching of embryos”, published on 11 July 2014, where the text reads: This is a case of “mistaken” heterologous fertilisation (the mother carries embryos that are genetically not hers nor her husband’s or partner’s) or “mistaken” surrogate mother (the genetic parents produce embryos that are implanted into the uterus of another woman who carries them for gestation) in a procedure for which no consent has been given, which appears to lead to a position of uncertainty with regard to the maternity and paternity faced with a legislative gap that needs to be filled in terms of interpretation”.

Thus, in its order of 8 August 2014, the court of Rome, after establishing that currently applicable Italian law neither addresses nor explicitly regulates the circum-stance in question, stated that it would be unreasonable in relationships of filiation to assign superordinate status to the principle of genetic truth over other conflicting interests, because “recognising the prevalence of the genetic mother, juridical legitimacy would be attributed to a coercive substitutive maternity, with the renunciation having been imposed on a child that the biological mother

brought into the world”. This solution would be “totally unreconcilable with the right of the mother carrying the foetus to the intangibility of her body and, therefore, to being able to make every decision relating to her preg-nancy, as well as being seriously damaging to the human dignity of the expectant mother”.

With an appropriate reference to scientific literature, the order also points out that it is in the uterus that the symbiotic relationship is created between the unborn child and the expectant mother and that it is only the latter who can breastfeed the child.

After all, – reads the order – the figures of genetic mother, uterine mother and social mother (i.e. a woman who, wishing to have a child but unable to procreate one, “commissions” a child from the genetic mother) do not always coincide. However, art. 269, subsection 3, of the Civil Code, unchanged from its original wording even fol-lowing the reform on filiation, as per Legislative Decree 154/2013, enshrines the principle by which it is birth that determines motherhood.

For this reason, the judge dismissed the couple’s appeal and left the twins to the mother who had given birth to them and to her partner, sustaining that any interim injunction would have prejudiced the stability of the minors’ status and their right to life with what should be considered their family.

3 Conclusions

The uncommon split in natural contribution between genetic and uterine mothers imposes the need to make a “tragic choice between two partial truths” [4] that are both of equal importance. Whilst the passing on of genetic makeup to the unborn child depends on the former, it is the latter who prepares him/her for life, through the unbreakable bond that is created, during pregnancy, between her own vital functions and those of the foetus she is carrying in her womb.

Albeit, in the light of the abovementioned legally cod-ified principle (art. 269, subsection 3, Civil Code), a strong orientation has been established, also in the last hypoth-esis, towards attribution of maternity to the birth mother [5-8], such a solution has not failed to give rise to differ-ences between scholars.

Those who highlight the essential and conditioning value – aimed at possibly identifying the true mother based on the dual biological and social factor – of a precise legislative ruling oriented in this direction [9], are opposed by those who, by taking a different path,

con-Brought to you by | Sistema Bibliotecario di Ateneo Authenticated Download Date | 4/19/18 10:09 AM

(3)

Gestational surrogacy   121

sider, on the basis of existing law (de jure condito), the “gynaecological” fact of birth to be insufficient [10-12].

From the latter perspective, it has been observed that the law’s attribution of maternity to the birth mother is only apparent. The principle that underpins the rule con-tained in art. 269, subsection 3 of the Civil Code should, in fact, be read in the sense that the mother is the woman who gives birth to the product of the fertilisation of her (own) oocyte. If Italian lawmakers did not expressly require the subsistence of such a coincidence between birth mother and genetic mother, this would have depended – it has been said – exclusively on the fact that it was impossible for them to imagine the emergence of a different situation.

Therefore, in cases where, as a consequence of the practice of leasing out the uterus, such a coincidence does not effectively subsist, the choice between the two women should be made taking account of the interest of the child that is to be born, who, according to the orien-tation considered, is identified in the attribution of par-enthood to the genetic mother (provided that she is the commissioning mother) [13]. Indeed, only the latter would have an emotional, as well as biological, bond with the child, considering not only her genetic but also social con-tribution – having consciously and responsibly given rise to the causal chain of actions that conclude with the birth – made with the creation of the embryo [14].

All in all, however, attribution of legal maternity to the birth mother remains the most accredited thesis. Among the arguments in support of this option, it appears that particular importance should be given to the fact that the child acquires legal capacity at the moment of separa-tion from the maternal womb, without minimally pointing to the circumstance that the birth follows the implanting of another woman’s ovum into the gestational mother’s body [15]. It can be observed, furthermore, that it is in the behaviour of the gestational mother that there is a need to identify the element of personal responsibility in order to define the juridical concept of maternity [8]. It is thanks to the contribution of the gestational mother that the life of the person springs forth and develops in a symbiotic bond with the mother up to the moment of birth [5,6,16]. The birth mother is not a machine for producing children, nor is she an animal whose womb can be used to provide a purely material service [5]. But, above all, it is the ges-tational mother who must remain the “arbiter” of the destiny of the pregnancy [17].

Conflicts of interest: The authors have no conflicts of

interest to declare.

References

[1] Ioratti Ferrari E., in Rodotà S., Zatti P. (directed by) Treaty of Biodiritto, The Government of the Body [Trattato di Biodiritto, Il Governo del corpo], Giuffrè, Milan, 2011

[2] Piras M, Delbon P, Bin P, et al. Voluntary termination of pregnancy (medical or surgical abortion): forensic medicine issues. Open Medicine. 2016;11(1):321-326

[3] Stagliano R., Embryos exchanged: four parents and no certainty [Embrioni scambiati: quattro genitori e nessuna certezza], Il Venerdi di Repubblica, 1 May 2014

[4] Patti S., Truth and legal status of the person [Verità e stato giuridico della persona], Riv. dir. civ., 1988

[5] Trabucchi A., Artificial procreation and the legal concept of motherhood and fatherhood [Procreazione artificiale e il concetto giuridico di maternità e di paternità], Riv. dir. civ., 1982

[6] Bianca M., State of people [Stato delle persone], in Artificial procreation and interventions in human genetics [Procreazione artificiale e interventi nella genetica umana], Cedam, Padua, 1987

[7] Comporti M., Constitutional and civilizational profiles [Profili costituzionalistici e civilistici], Justitia, 1985, 336

[8] Calogero M., Artificial procreation. A recognition of the problems [La procreazione artificiale. Una ricognizione dei problemi], Giuffrè, Milan, 1989

[9] Quadri E., Reproduction techniques between current law and possible legislative options [Le tecniche di riproduzione tra diritto vigente e possibili opzioni legislative], Famiglia e ordinamento civile, 1999, 259

[10] Clarizia R., Artificial procreation and protection of the minor [Procreazione artificiale e tutela del minore], Giuffrè, Milan, 1988

[11] Gorassini A., Heterologous artificial procreation and primary parental relationships [Procreazione artificiale eterologa e rapporti parentali primari], Dir.fam. pers., 1987, 1249 [12] Baldini G., Will and procreation: reconnaissance of the main

issues in surrogacy [Volontà e procreazione: ricognizione delle principali questioni in tema di surrogazione di maternità], Dir. fam. 1998, 780

[13] Vercellone P., Assisted fertilization and family status [Fecondazione assistita e status familiari], Proceedings of the conference Fertilization assisted: a bill to be discussed, Pisa, 30 January – 2 February 1997

[14] Santosuosso F., Medically assisted procreation [La procreazione medicalmente assistita], Giuffrè, Milan, 2004 [15] Dogliotti M., Artificial insemination and relationships of

filiation [Inseminazione artificiale e rapporti di filiazione], Giur. it., 1991, 1(2), 73

[16] Paternoster M., Saccone G., Maruotti G.M., Bianco C., Casella C., Buccelli C., Martinelli P., Ethical challenges in pregnant women with brain injury, The Journal of Maternal-Fetal & Neonatal Medicine, 2017, DOI: 10.1080/14767058.2017.1339271

[17] Scia F., Medically assisted procreation and embryo status [Procreazione medicalmente assistita e status del generato], Jovene, 2010, 281

Brought to you by | Sistema Bibliotecario di Ateneo Authenticated Download Date | 4/19/18 10:09 AM

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

As both cAS lines showed the same phenotype in terms of resistance, partial impairment of HR cell death and lower PR-1 induction, the cAS3 line (thereafter cAS) was selected for

Abbreviations of lithostratigraphic units: TIT, Tithonian limestones; GRA, Cime de la Graye Limestone; CLA, Clarissia Formation; GV, Grès Verts (GVa,

limestones and marly limestones, locally encrusted by Microcodium, in the Entracque Unit (Caire di Porcera); more or less dolomitized Garbella Limestone in the central part of the

(1) Following the entry into force of Directive 2004/40/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council 2 , stakeholders, in particular those in the medical community,

impiegati in servizi istituzionali delle Forze di polizia dello Stato, della Dogana, del Corpo nazionale dei vigili del fuoco, del Dipartimento della protezione civile o in

Qatari academic and research centers together with the other major players in Qatar, should collaborate to work on producing specific national guidelines on genetic testing

In the Standard Model these phases occur only in the CKM matrix which is part of the electroweak sector of the theory, hence these are often called “weak phases.” The weak phase of

The Assembly should thus urge member States and the European Union to take certain steps with respect to the development and allocation of Covid-19 vaccines, to ensure a high