• Non ci sono risultati.

In order to stand up you must keep cycling: Change and coordination in complex evolving economies

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "In order to stand up you must keep cycling: Change and coordination in complex evolving economies"

Copied!
12
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

ContentslistsavailableatScienceDirect

Structural

Change

and

Economic

Dynamics

jo u r n al hom e p a g e :w w w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / s c e d

In

order

to

stand

up

you

must

keep

cycling:

Change

and

coordination

in

complex

evolving

economies

G.

Dosi

b,∗

,

M.E.

Virgillito

a,b

aInstituteofEconomicPolicy,Universita’CattolicadelSacroCuoreViaLudovicoNecchi,520123,Milan,Italy

bInstituteofEconomics,ScuolaSuperioreSant’Anna,PiazzaMartiridellaLiberta’33,I-56127,Pisa,Italy

a

r

t

i

c

l

e

i

n

f

o

Articlehistory: Received23January2017 Accepted14June2017 Availableonlinexxx JELclassification: O1 O3 P1 Keywords: Change Coordination EvolutionaryEconomics Socio-economicsystems

a

b

s

t

r

a

c

t

Inthisworkwediscussthemainbuildingblocks,achievementsandchallengesofanevolutionary interpretationoftherelationbetweenmechanismsofcoordinationanddriversofchangeinmodern economies,seenascomplexevolvingsystems.Itisanevidentstylisedfactofmoderneconomicsystems thatthereareforcesatworkwhichkeepthemtogetherandmakethemgrowdespiterapidand pro-foundmodificationsoftheirindustrialstructures,socialrelations,techniquesofproduction,patternsof consumption.Wesuggestthatafruitfulinterpretationofthetwoprocessesrestsinwhatwecallthe “bicycleconjecture”:inordertostandupyoumustkeepcycling.However,changesandtransformationare bynature“disequilibrating”forces.Thustheremustbeotherfactorswhichmaintainrelativelyordered configurationsofthesystemandallowabroadconsistencybetweentheconditionsofmaterial repro-duction(includingincomedistributions,accumulation,availabletechniques)andthethreadofsocial relations.

©2017ElsevierB.V.Allrightsreserved.

1. Changeandcoordination:anintroduction

Inthisworkwediscussthemainbuildingblocks,achievements and challengesof anevolutionaryinterpretationoftherelation betweenmechanisms of coordination and drivers of change in economiesseenascomplex evolvingsystems.Certainly,in eco-nomicsystemsthereareforcesatworkwhichkeepthemtogether andmakethemgrowinrelativelyorderedmanners(oftenbutnot always)despiterapidandprofoundmodificationsoftheir indus-trialstructures,socialrelations,techniquesofproduction,patterns ofconsumption,whichassuch,are“disequilibrating”forces.Thus, theremustbefactorswhichmaintainrelativelyordered configu-rationsofthesystemandallowabroadconsistencybetweenthe conditionsof materialreproduction (including income distribu-tions,accumulation,availabletechniques)andthethreadofsocial relations.

Verydaringly,indeed,thearticleattemptstoaddressthetwo basicquestionsatthecoreofthewholeeconomicdisciplinesince itsinceptionwhichregard,first,thedriversandpatternsofchange ofthecapitalistmachineofproductionandinnovationand,second,

∗ Correspondingauthor.

E-mailaddresses:gdosi@santannapisa.it(G.Dosi),

mariaenrica.virgillito@unicatt.it(M.E.Virgillito).

themechanismsofcoordinationamongamultitudeofself-seeking economic agentsoften characterizedby conflictinginterests.Of course,ofcrucialimportancearetheanswerswhichdiverse the-ories offer to these two questions, but equally important, the relationspurportedbetweenthetwo.

Theinterplay betweenchangeandcoordination, wellbefore EvolutionaryEconomics,hasbeenatthecoreoftheanalysesof AdamSmithandlaterMarxandSchumpeter.Changeand trans-formationoftechnologies,industrialstructures,organizationsand socialrelationsshapetheevolutionofthecapitalistsystemwhich ischaracterizedbyprocessesofendogenousself-sustainedgrowth, punctuatedbysmallandbigcrises.Theprocessofeconomicgrowth isallbutsteady:

Industrialmutation–ifImayusethebiologicalterm–that incessantlyrevolutionisestheeconomicstructurefromwithin, incessantlydestroyingtheoldone,incessantlycreatinganew one.ThisprocessofCreativeDestructionistheessentialfact aboutcapitalism. [Schumpeter(1947),p.83]

Interestingly,AdamSmithbeginshisWealthofNationswitha detailedanalysisofthedriversofchange–inparticularthepositive feedbacksbetweendivisionoflabour,mechanisation,productivity growthanddemandgrowth,whileissuesofcoordinationare dis-cussedmuchlater,buildingonsuchadynamicbackground.Much laterand fromaquitedifferentangle,Keynestooneverdreamt

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.strueco.2017.06.003

(2)

ofseparating“whatkeepsthesystemtogether”from“whatkeeps itgoing”:infact,thepropertiesofshortertermcoordinationwere derivedfromthepropertiesofcapitalaccumulationandtheanimal spiritsdrivingit.

Aswellknown,thecurrentdominanttheoreticalcreedisvery muchontheanalytical oppositetoSmithand Keynes.It builds ontheseparationbetween“coordination”and“dynamics”, start-ing from the former, and assuming away the latter in a first approximation.The “coordinationresearch program”,soon cul-minated into the Arrow-Debreu-McKenzie General Equilibrium model,hasbeenindeedanelegantandinstitutionallyvery parsimo-niousdemonstrationofthepossibilityofequilibriumcoordination amongstdecentralisedagents.However,subsequent,basically neg-ative,resultshaveshownthegeneralimpossibilityofmovingfrom existencetheoremstothatsortofimplicitdynamicscapturedby proofs of globalor local stability – loosely speaking,the prop-ertyofthesystem,whenscrambled,togetbacktoitsequilibrium state.Quitethecontrary,even empiricallyfar-fetchedprocesses suchastâtonnements(withtheomniscientWalrasianauctioneer proclaimingequilibriumvstransactionwhenheseesthem)in gen-eraldonotconverge.Evenmorepowerfully,someofthefounding fathersofGEthemselveshaveshownthatexistencedoesnotbear anyimplicationintermsoftheshapeofexcessdemandfunctions (thisiswhattheSonnenschein-Mantel-Debreutheoremimplies). Puttingitshortly,ingeneralevenforgetlocalstability!Conversely, anycareful lookatthetollrequirementswhich sheerexistence entails–intermsofinformationandrationality–highlightsthe extenttowhichGEisabeautifulbutextremelyfragilecreature, certainlyunabletowithholdtheweightofanyaccountofthe coor-dinationprocessesoftheeconomyasawholeandevenlessso, toofferanyseriousmicro-foundationtotransformingeconomies undergoingvariousformsofinnovation.Infact,iftheconditions– intermofrationality,characteristicsoftheexchange,etc.–required inrealitywereevenvaguelyasstringentasthoserequiredinGE models,probablynoonewouldbeeverobservedintherealworld! Here,weproposetoreverttotheoldSmithianstyleof interpre-tation,beginningwiththeunderstandingofthedriversofchange andonlynexttrytounderstandthe(imperfect)coordinating prop-erties of the economic systems. It is what we call the bicycle conjecture:inordertostandupyoumustkeepcycling.However,in ordertooperationalizetheconjecture,verytalltasksconcern,first, theidentificationof“whatistheretobeexplained”–thatisthe empiricalandhistoricalstylizedfactsatdifferentlevelof aggre-gationanddifferenttimescales–and,second,explore howwe theoreticallyaccountforthem.

In contemporaryeconomies oneobserves that technological knowledgeistoagoodextentincorporatedintocorporate organi-zations,intheformofsharedcognitiveframesandorganizational routines,evolvingovertimeasaresultoflearning,innovationand adaptation.Inturn,such(heterogeneous)firmsoperatein compet-itiveenvironmentswhichcontributetodeterminetheirrevealed performances–intermsofgrowth,profitabilityandsurvival prob-abilities – and collectivelythe evolution of thewhole industry towhichtheybelong.Indeed,theevolutionofdiverseindustries drivenbytechnologicalandorganizationallearningisalsoatthe heartoftheprocessofdevelopmentandmacroeconomicgrowth.

Howdoesthetheoryaccountsfortheforegoinghistorical pat-ternsandstylisedfacts?Undertheprevailingparadigm,itdoesthat tryingtorationaliseeachempiricalregularitywith“thecombined assumptionsofmaximizingbehaviour,marketequilibriumand sta-blepreferences,usedrelentlesslyandconsistently”(Becker,1976). Here,weproposeanalternativeviewlargelybasedonopposite buildingblocks,aimedatunderstandingtheeconomyasa com-plexevolvingsystem.Inanutshell,suchaperspectiveattemptsto understanda wide setofeconomicphenomena –rangingfrom microeconomicbehaviourstothefeaturesofindustrialstructures

anddynamics,allthewaytothepropertiesofaggregategrowth anddevelopment–asoutcomesoffar-from-equilibrium interac-tionsamongheterogeneousagents,characterizedbyendogenous preferences,most“oftenboundedlyrational”butalwayscapable oflearning,adaptingandinnovatingwithrespecttotheir under-standingsoftheworldinwhichtheyoperate,thetechnologiesthey master,theirorganizational forms and theirbehavioural reper-toires.

Inthefollowingweshalldiscussthebuildingblocksofsucha perspective(Section2),someofitsdomainofapplications(Section 3),concludingwithsomechallengesahead(Section4).1

2. Theeconomyasacomplexevolvingsystem

Startwiththemostminimalistnotionofcomplexity:itstandsat theveryleastforthefactthattheeconomyiscomposedbymultiple interactingactors.AsH.Simon,alsocitedinKirman(2016),putsit: RoughlybyacomplexsystemImeanonemadeupofalarge numberofpartsthatinteractinanon-simpleway.Insuch sys-tems,thewholeismorethanthesumoftheparts,notinan ultimatemetaphysicalsense,butintheimportantpragmatic sensethat,given thepropertiesof theparts andthelawsof theirinteraction,itisnotatrivialmattertoinfertheproperties ofthewhole. [Simon(1969),p.267]

Indeed, the properties of the whole are generally emergent properties,that iscollectivepropertiesstemmingfromthelocal interaction among multiple agents, which however cannot be attributedtotheintentionalityofanyagentsorcollectionofthem (moreinLane,1993;NicolisandPrigogine,1977;Camazineetal., 2001).Notethatcomplexityandemergencedonotpreventatallthe searchforpossiblelawsofmotionofanysystem,buttheydorule outany“antropomorphization”oftheinterpretationofwhatever dynamics,sofamiliarincontemporarytheory.Moreover, evolu-tionentailsthatanyassumptionof“givenfundamentals”(including technologiesandpreferences)inmostcircumstancesimpliesa sig-nificantviolencetotheobjectofstudy.Ofcourseforanyanalysis ofacomplex andevolvingeconomyonehastogowellbeyond theSchumpeter/Samuelsonseparationbetweencoordinationand change.The(imperfect)coordinatingfeatures ofthesystemare fundamentallyshapedbyitsevolvingnature.Therelativelyorderly propertiesofcapitalisteconomiesderivefromitsbeinginmotion. Thisistherelativeorderof“restlesscapitalism”(Metcalfe,1998).So forexample,pricesmoveroughlyinlinewiththeaveragecostsof productionwhichinturndependontheunderlying (technology-specificandsector-specific)ratesofprocessinnovation.Demand patternsareshapedbytheensuingpricesand,possiblyevenmore importantly,bythetrajectoriesinproductinnovation.Grossand netlabourdemandareaffectedbythedoublenatureoftechnical progressasa“labour saver”and asa“demandcreator”.Among manyothers, theseareallfeatures ofimperfectcoordinationin evolvingsystems.Andsoarethedistributionalpropertiesof what-everstatisticsoneconomicvariableswhichstempreciselyfrom thefactthatthesystemischangingallthetimeinitsprocessand productinnovations,consumptionpatterns,organizationalforms.

2.1. Routines,rulesofthumb,heuristics

Thefirstquestiononeneedstoaddressis:howdoagentsbehave? InthetraditionofEvolutionaryEconomics,routines,rulesofthumb andheuristicsarethecorepillarsdescribingthebehaviourofagents.

1ComplementarydiscussionsareShaikh(2016),Pianta(2017)andseveral

con-tributionsintheprospectiveofstructuralchangeandatheoreticalessayonthe

(3)

InCohenetal.(1996),S.Winterprovidesaconceptualclassification ofthethreelattercategories:(i)routinesareautomated,repetitive andunconsciousbehaviourswhichhoweverrequireahighlevel ofinformationprocessing(e.g.workinginanassemblylines, mak-ingairlinereservationorbanktransactions);(ii)rulesofthumb arerelativelysimpledecisionruleswhichrequirelowerlevelsof informationprocessinginvolvesomequantitativedecisions(e.g. theshareofR&Dovertotalsales,thefixedmark-up);(iii)heuristics areguidelinesandbehaviouralorientationsadoptedtoface prob-lemsolvingwhichdonotprovideanyready-to-usesolution,but onlybroadstrategies(e.g.indecisionmaking,“Dowhatwedidthe lasttimeasimilarproblemcameup”,inbargaining,“Askalways morethanwhatyoudesire”,intechnology,“Makeitsmaller/Make itfaster”).

Thesethreeelementsarethetraitsoforganizationsandthey entailboth (i) problem-solving action patternsand (ii) mecha-nismsofcontrolandgovernance.Theconflictingnatureofinterests, knowledge,andpreferencesinsideorganizations,likefirms,iswell summarizedinMarch(1962):ratherthanmaximizingunits,firms arebetterrepresentedintermsofpoliticalstructuresdisplaying(i) thetoleranceofinconsistenciesinbothgoalsanddecisionsover timeandinsidetheorganization,(ii)decentralisedgoalsand deci-sionswithloosecross-connections,(iii)slowlyshiftsovertimein responsetoshiftsinthecoalitionButgivensuchanatureofthe firmhowcanwemodelitsbehaviour?

Conversely,intherecentyears,theintroductionofthe com-puterandthecomputerprogrammodeltotherepertoireofthe theoristhaschangeddramaticallythetheoreticalpotentialof processdescriptionmodelsofconflictsystems.Complex pro-cessdescriptionmodelsoforganizationalbehaviourpermita developmentofamicro-economictheoryofthefirm. [March (1962)pp.674–675]

In tracing the Agenda for Evolutionary Economics, Winter (2017)emphasizeshowtheuseofthemaximization procedure isintrinsicallyinappropriatetostudythebehaviourofthefirms. March(1962)sharedlongagothesameconcern:

Generallyspeaking,profitmaximizationcanbemadeperfectly meaningful(withsomequalifications);butwhenmade mean-ingful, it usually turns out to beinvalid as a description of firmbehaviour.[...]Withfewexceptions,modernobserversof actualfirmbehaviourreportpersistentandsignificant contra-dictionsbetweenfirmbehaviourandtheclassicalassumptions. [March(1962)p.670]

Theprofit-seekingmaximizingbehaviouroffirmsiscarefully debunkedinWinter(1964)whopointsattwolinesofcriticism: first, even though it is reasonable to conceive firms as having goals, isnot appropriateto assumethat theoperationalgoalis profitmaximization.Rather,organizationstrytosatisfysome objec-tivesoperationallydifferentfromprofitmaximization.Second,ina worldcharacterizedbycontinuouschangeitisimpossibletopursue anyprofitmaximizationforthelackofanythoroughunderstanding ofthedetailedstructuresofever-changingworlds.

InhisNobelMemorialLectureSimon(1979)stresseshowthe failureofomniscienceare“failuresofknowingallofthepossible alternatives,uncertaintyaboutexogenousevents,andinabilityto calculateconsequences”(p.502).Resultsfromavastliteraturein experimentaleconomicsshowthat:

itisnot thatpeopledonot gothroughthecalculationsthat wouldberequiredbythesubjectiveexpectedutilitydecision– neoclassicalthoughthasneverclaimedthattheydid.Whathas beenshownisthattheydonotevenbehaveasiftheyhave car-riedoutthosecalculations,andthatresultisadirectrefutation oftheneoclassicalassumptions. [Simon(1979),p.507]

There are good reasons why agents in such evolutionary environment adopt robust and rather information-independent heuristics.which

[is]astrategythatignorespartoftheinformation,withthegoal ofmakingdecisionsmorequickly,frugally,and/oraccurately than more complex methods. [Gigerenzer and Gaissmaier (2011),p.454]

Note that, heuristics are not “biases” yielding sub-optimal behaviours(asonewouldgatherfromKahneman,2002,orfromthe bulkofbehaviouraleconomics),butmightbe“locallyex-post opti-malstrategies”thatoutperformpurportedly“rational”choicesin largeworldscharacterizedbysubstantiveandproceduraluncertainty (DosiandEgidi,1991),aswellasdriversofmajorcontagion-fuelled disasters.

Aclearcutexampleoftheuseofheuristicsintradingbehaviours is highlightedin finance.As DeMiguel etal. (2009) show,over a sample of seven datasets, the simple 1/N rule outperforms theMarkowitz Portfolio strategy infourteenalternative portfo-liospecifications.“Rational”allocationstrategiesyieldveryhigh estimationerrorsinthevariance-covariancematrices.Infact,in changinganddistributionalvariantworlds,thesimple1/Nstrategy happenstobemuchmorerobustandlesserrorprone.

2.2. Coordinationvis-à-visequilibrium

ThetermEvolutionaryrecallsthefieldofBiologywhereinthe processesofmutationandselectionamongspeciesareatthecore ofevolution.AlreadyintheMarshalliandefinitionofEconomics,the latterwasconceivedtobemuchmoreclosertoBiologyratherthan MechanicalPhysics:

TheMecca oftheeconomistliesin economicbiology rather thanineconomicdynamics.Butbiologicalconceptionsaremore complexthanthose ofmechanics;a volumeonFoundations mustthereforegivearelativelylargeplacetomechanical analo-gies;andfrequentuseismadeoftheterm“equilibrium,”which suggestssomethingofstaticalanalogy.Thisfact,combinedwith thepredominantattentionpaidinthepresentvolumetothe normalconditionsoflifeinthemodernage,hassuggestedthe notionthatitscentralideais“statical”,ratherthan “dynami-cal”.Butinfactitisconcernedthroughoutwiththeforcesthat causemovement:anditskey-noteisthatofdynamics,rather thanstatics. [Marshall(1890),vol.1,p.xiv]

Nonetheless, the goal of neoclassical economic analysis has beenconfinedtostudymarketcoordinationasanequilibrium out-come. Coordinationis not aneasy task: after all theeconomic processesaretheresultsofindividualdecisionsmaking charac-terizedbyex-antepossibleinconsistencies.But,economicagents coordinatethemselvesinsideorganizations,institutions,societies. Whydoweobservesuchemergenceoforder(wherethe mean-ingofordershouldbeaccuratelydistinguishedfromthenotionof equilibrium)?

Aswell known,theneoclassical response totheproblemof coordinationhasbeenbymeansofprices:exchangeamong decen-tralised agents, whoare pursuingtheirown utilitymaximizing transactions,aresupposedtoyieldequilibriumoutcomes(thatis anequilibriumsystemofpricesandquantities):marketsclearafter alldesiredtransactionshaveoccurred,sothatnobodydesiresmore thanwhatsheobtainedaftertheexchange.Apartfromtheeasy criticismontherealismofthisapproach,andparticularlyonthe validity of theassumptions of perfectcompetition and rational expectations,whichhavealsobeentakenupintheneoclassical analysisitself(takingonboard,tovaryingdegrees,imperfect com-petitionandasymmetricinformation),theprocessesofinteractions andevolutionofbehavioursisremarkablyneglected.

(4)

Ifdynamics and interactions count,the conceptequilibrium oughttobere-thoughtandsubstitutedbysomenotionof coor-dinationpatterns(moreinDosiandOrsenigo,1988).Infact,the usualconcernforequilibriumdoesnotfindmuchplaceinsidethe evolutionarytheorizing.Withoutpostulatinganyex-antemarket clearingcondition,necessarytoendogenouslydetermineaclosed solution for the unknown variables (e.g. prices and quantities), evolutionaryeconomic modelsare meantat understandingthe coordinationpatternsthatresultoutoftheinteractionof heteroge-neousagents.Theanalysisisnotinterestedinfindinganydeducted equilibriumsolution,butratherinidentifyingemergentproperties. AccordingtoLane(1993),emergentpropertiesare:

[...]afeatureofahistorythat(i)canbedescribedintermsof aggregate-levelconstructs,withoutreferencetotheattributes ofspecificMEs(MicrolevelEntities);(ii)persistsfortime peri-odsmuchgraterthanthetimescaleappropriatefordescribing theunderlingmicro-interactions;and(iii)defiesexplanationby reductiontothesuperpositionof“built-in”micro-propertiesof theAW[ArtificialWorlds]. [Lane(1993),pp.90–91]

So,forexample,inThe‘SchumpetermeetingKeynes’models (buildingonDosietal.,2010),webuildanartificialworldpopulated bymachine-producerswhomakenewcapitalgoodsand machine-buyerswhoorderthelattertoproducehomogeneousgoodsold totheworkers.Thedynamicsofaggregateoutput,consumption andinvestmentwhichtypicallyexhibitsustainedlongrungrowth andfluctuationsareemergentpropertiesnotdirectlylinkedtothe attributesofthemicrolevelentities.

The emergent properties are conceived to be meta-stable andnot uniqueor stableequilibria: whenever attributesatthe microlevel are changed also the emergent properties can be fairlydifferent.Artificialeconomiesaremainlyhigh-dimensional stochasticmodels,hardlytreatableanalytically.Then,asymptotic convergencesomesteady-statestabilityaregenerallyimpossible toobtain.Rather,theconditionsunderwhichorderedpatternsor trajectoriesemergearetherelevantquestions addressedbythe analysis.

2.3. Heterogeneityandinteraction

Heterogeneity is a general feature of complex evolving economiesinalldomainsofobservation. Itconcerns productiv-itydispersionsatalllevelsofaggregation,organizational forms, personalandfunctionalincomedistributions.

Inturn,theseheterogeneousagentsinteract, contrarytothe standardmodelswherethereisnosignofsuchinteractions.The absenceofanyexplicitcoordinationprocessinthelattermodels isdiscussedinKirman (1992),in hisdevastating critiqueofthe representativeagent(RA):

Paradoxically,thesortofmacroeconomicmodelswhichclaim togiveapictureofeconomicreality(albeitasimplifiedpicture) havealmostnoactivitywhichneedssuchcoordination.Thisis becausetypicallytheyassumethatthechoicesofallthediverse agentsinonesectorconsumersforexamplecanbeconsidered asthechoices ofone“representative”standardutility maxi-mizingindividualwhosechoicescoincidewiththeaggregate choicesoftheheterogeneousindividuals. [Kirman(1992),p. 117]

AsKirman(1992)shows,theRAapparatusisnotsimply unre-alisticbutwrong becausenot well-suitedtostudyproblems of emergence and particularly of lack of coordination like unem-ployment,income inequality,and in generalaggregatedemand externalities. Related, intrinsic, theoretical flaws of the repre-sentativeagentconcern(i)thesymmetry ofbehaviourbetween individualandaggregatesrationality;(ii)thereactionoftheRAto

policychangesmaybequitedifferentfromtheaggregatereaction oftheindividuals;(iii)theorderedofchoicesoftheRAmaynot guaranteetheindividualpreferencerankingorders;(iv)whenever onedoeshypothesistesting,tryingtocomparethemodelwiththe data,themodellerdoesnotknowif,incaseofrejection,onehasto rejectspecificallytheRAorsomeotherbehaviouralhypotheses.

If theobjective of theneoclassical modelleris to reachthe exactmicrofoundations,ensured bytheoptimizationprocedure performedbytheRA,thelatterprocedureintrinsicallycontradicts theinnermeaningofmicrofoundation.Allinall,adirect conse-quenceoftheRAisthatthetradeconundrum,accordingtowhich noexchangeshouldpersistentlyoccurinequilibrium.Transactions areonlymildturbulencesaroundtheequilibriumpoint.

ResultsfromtheGeneralEquilibriumscholarsthemselves high-lightedbytheSonnenschein–Mantel–Debreutheoremsshowthat assumedmicroproperties,liketransitivityofpreferences,which ifviolatedcouldleadtomultiplicityofequilibria,arenot guaran-teedbytheaggregationprocess(unlessfurtherrestrictionssuch ashomotheticutilityfunctionsetc.ofallmicroagentsare postu-lated).Theonlyviableset-upexploredintheneoclassicalmodelsto overcometheaggregationproblemhasbeenreducingthe dimen-sionalityfromnpotentiallyheterogeneousindividuals(atleasttwo intheoriginalGeneralEquilibriumprogram)toone.Inthislatter case,theexcessdemandfunctionwillobviouslysatisfyallthe reg-ularityconditionsrequiredtogetuniquenessandstabilityofthe equilibrium.

Inanalternativeperspective,Kirman (1992)discussesunder whichcircumstancesaggregationamongheterogeneousagentsis sufficienttohaveawellbehavedaggregatedemandfunction:

Onceoneallowsfordifferentmicro-behaviorandforthefact that different agents face differing and independent micro-variablesthen[...]complexaggregatedynamicsmayarisefrom simple,[...],individualbehavior. [Kirman(1992)p.127] Becker(1962)intheearlysixtiesalreadyemphasizedhow“the lawofdemand”maybejust theeffectthat pricechangesexert onthebudgetconstraint,andnotberelatedtoanydecisionrules: thenegativedemandslopeisindependentfromtherationalor irra-tionalcontentofthedecisionrules.Asimilartheoreticaldiscussion isinGrandmont(1991),whoshowstherelativelyunimportance ofthemaximizationofautilityfunction,andconverselythe rele-vanceofthesimplesatisfactionofthebudgetconstrainttoobtain well-behavedaggregatedemandfunctions.Theconditionsunder whichaggregationyields“wellbehaved”aggregatedemand func-tionsindependentlyofthefinespecificationofmicrobehaviours areshowedinHildenbrand(1994).

Moregenerally,theinteractionamongheterogeneousagents, byitself,allowsfortheemergenceofdynamicssuchasendogenous cyclesandfluctuations,withouttheneedofexternalshockshitting thesystem(seeDosietal.,2010amongothers).

2.4. Innovationandgrowth

Theprocessofeconomicchangeasbeenatthecoreofthe“Grand EvolutionaryProject”atleastsincetheseminalworkbyNelsonand Winter(1982).Theearlygrowthneoclassicalmodelshavebeen identifyinginthesocalledSolowresidualor,usingthefelicitous expressionbyAbramovitz (1956),themeasure ofourignorance, theunaccountedsourceofeconomicgrowth.Rathersurprisingly, theearlyscholarsofgrowththeorydecidedtoshelvetheenquiry exactlyonthesourceofeconomicgrowth,treating“technological changeasaresidualneutrino”:

Theneutrinoisafamousexampleinphysicsofalabellingof anerrortermthatprovedfruitful.Physicistsultimatelyfound neutrinos,andthepropertiestheyturnedouttohavewere

(5)

con-sistentwithpreservation ofthebasictheoryasamendedby acknowledgementoftheexistenceofneutrinos.Amajor por-tionoftheresearchbyeconomistsonprocessesofeconomic growthsincethelate1950shasbeenconcernedwithmore accu-ratelyidentifyingandmeasuringtheresidualcalledtechnical change,andbetterspecifyinghowphenomenarelatedto tech-nicaladvancefitintogrowththeorymoregenerally.[Nelsonand Winter(1982),p.198]

Aftertheearlygrowthmodelsofexogenoustechnicalchangeá laSolow,the1990ssawtheflourishingofthesocalled“endogenous growththeory”attemptingtoincorporateinherently Schumpete-rianthemes intomainstream models.Nonetheless, endogenous growthmodelsdo notseemabletoaccountforsomeelements typicallycharacterizingtheprocessesofinnovationandgrowth.

Asoneoftheearlyevolutionarymodelsoftechnologicalchange (Silverberg and Verspagen,1994) puts it, requirementsneeded to genuinely model endogenous growth are (i) coexistence of manytechnologiesandtechniquesofproductionatanygiventime period;(ii)nouniqueproductionfunction(coexistenceof multi-pletechniquesofproductionevenatthefrontier);(iii)dependence oftheaggregaterateoftechnicalchangeondiffusionof innova-tion,notsimplyontheinstantaneousinnovationrate;(iv)ifthe innovativeeffortisrepresentedbyastochasticdrawfrom proba-bilitydistributions,theparametersofthedistributionshavetobe unknowntotheagents.

Infact,suchrequirementsappropriatelymapintoaseriesof attributesoftechnology(seealsobelow):searchanddiscoveryof innovationareprocessesintrinsicallycharacterizedbyKnigthian uncertainty whereinthereis noexact correspondence between ex-anteeffortandex-postperformance;thereisnoconvergence towardanoptimalcapital/labourratiowhichdefinestheunique techniqueadoptedbytheusers,butratheraconstellationsof tech-niquesofproductionareemployedbydifferentfirms.

In our evolutionary perspective it is the contribution of knowledge, transferred into the innovative activities which is “responsible”fortheneutrino.Andknowledgeis avery special entitywhichis notcharacterizedbyscarcityandbydiminishing returns,overturning theoldperceptionofeconomicsasthe sci-enceofallocationofscarceresources.Ifknowledgeandinnovation becomethemaindeterminantsofeconomicgrowth,then abun-danceand dynamicincreasing returnsaretheruleand notthe exception:worlds withendogenousinnovationareubiquitously characterizedbydynamicincreasingreturns.Ifanything, innova-tionandknowledgeaccumulationarepreciselythedomainswhere thedismalprinciplesofscarcityandconservationaremassively violated:onecansystematicallygetmoreoutofless,and increas-ingreturnsarethegeneralrule.Thetheoreticalconsequencesare far-reaching.

Theknownpropertiesofinformation(itsnon-rivaluse, non-perishability, scale-freenessin its application etc.),when taken seriously,implythattheusualGeneralEquilibriumpropertiescan beruledout.InfactasdiscussedinRadnerandStiglitz(1984),it issufficienttoassumenonconvexitiesintheproductionfunction, duee.g.tothefixedcostofacquiringinformation.Givensuch non-convexities,theexistenceofequilibrium isnot guaranteed(see RothschildandStiglitz,1976anditsmanual-level acknowledge-mentinMas-Colelletal.,1995).Undernonconvextechnologies, thesupplycurveisnotequivalenttothemarginalcostfunction andtheintersectionwiththedemandcurveisnotensured.Arrow (1996)putsitbluntly:

[c]ompetitiveequilibriumisviableonlyifproduction possibil-itiesareconvexsets,thatisdonotdisplayincreasingreturn [...]withinformationconstantreturnsareimpossible.[...]The sameinformation[canbe]usedregardlessofthescaleof

pro-duction.Hencethereisanextremeformofincreasingreturns. [Arrow(1996)pp.647–648]

Infact,theexistenceofaconventionalGeneralEquilibriumis underminedinpresenceofinnovationevenneglectingthe increas-ingreturnspropertiesofinnovationitself:seeWinter(1971).In turn,increasingreturnsarelikelytodisplayasanorm,divergence ine.g.technologicalcapabilitiesandincomes.

2.5. History

Historyandpathdependencyareatthecenterstagein evo-lutionarytheorizing.So,forexample,inordertounderstandthe processof evolutionofa giventechnology, itisfundamental to understanditshistoricalorigin.David(1985)inhisseminal contri-butionemphasisestheimportanceofthesequenceofpastevents tointerpreteconomicsasanevolutionaryprocess:

Cicerodemandsofhistorians,first,thatwetelltruestories.I intendfullytoperformmydutyonthisoccasion,bygivingyoua homelypieceofnarrativeeconomichistoryinwhich“onedamn thingfollowsanother”.Themainpointofthestorywillbecome plainenough:itissometimesnotpossibletouncoverthelogic (orillogic) ofthe worldaroundus exceptby understanding howitgotthatway.Apath-dependentsequenceofeconomic changesisoneofwhichimportantinfluencesupontheeventual outcomecanbeexertedbytemporallyremoteevents,including happenings dominated bychance elementsrather than sys-tematicforces.Stochasticprocesseslikethatdonotconverge automaticallytoafixed-pointdistributionofoutcomes,andare callednon-ergodic.Insuchcircumstances“historicalaccidents” canneitherbeignored,norneatlyquarantinedforthepurpose ofeconomicanalysis;thedynamicprocessitselftakesonan essentiallyhistoricalcharacter. [David(1985),p.332] Inthisrespect,itistruethatNewEconomicHistoryhasbrought neoclassical economics to economic history (Fogel, 1965), but this hasbeen donein ourviewat an unreasonably highprice. Cliometrics,andlater,the“NewPoliticalEconomy”focusonthe quantitativeassessmentsofsociologicalandinstitutionalvariables whichareoftenthenbroughtintotheestimationoflong-run pro-ductionfunctions.Thepriceisthegeneralassumptionthatthere isafunctionallyinvariantgeneratingprocessandaninvariant eco-nomicrationalityapplicablefromStoneAgetribestoSpaceAge societies.

FreemanandLouc¸ã(2001)provideanenticing discussionon cliometrics.Aseriesofunsatisfyingoutputsofthisresearchstream culminatedwiththedescriptionofslaveryconditionasarational optimizingbehaviourforbothpartiesofthecontract:theowners werepraisedforthesuperiorityof theirmanagerialcapabilities andtheslavesforthesuperiorqualityofblacklabour.Cliometrics, apartfromabruptlyimportingthehomoeconomicus,carriedalso thenotionthatsheerrandomnesscouldadequatelycapture histori-calevents:first,someofthemareconsideredasrandom,exogenous eventsalteringtheregular(equilibrium)dynamics;second, histor-icaltimeseriesthemselvesareconsideredequivalenttoasample fromauniverseofalternativerealizationsofthesamestochastic process.Itisbasicallyanergodicworldwhere“deephistory”does notcount.

Landes(1994)emphasisestheinappropriatenessofthe fore-going research agenda in providing exhaustive explanation of historicalphenomena:

Iamconvincedthat thevery complexityoflargesystematic changesrequirescomplexexplanation:multiplecausesof shift-ingrelativeimportance,combinativedependency,...temporal dependency. [Landes(1994),p.653]

(6)

Complexevolvingsystemsaretypicallynon-ergodic,thus dis-playingpath-dependencies:whereyougodependsonwhereyou comefrom.

2.6. Institutions

Inabsenceofrational,profit-seekingmaximizingagents,what does it shape the behaviour of individuals and organizations? Howtherelativelyorderedpatternsabovementionedareableto emerge?Isitalltheoutcomeofself-organization?

Wehavebeenemphasizingabovehow(imperfect)coordination and(relatively)orderedchangecanbeinterpretedasphenomena ofself-organizationamongmultipleinteractingagents.However, suchprocessesareembeddedintoinstitutionswhichshape and constrainbehavioursandmodesofinteraction.Theyinclude mar-kets, but even more important, other non-market institutions rangingfromfamiliestofirms,fromunionstouniversitiestopublic agencies.

Inturn,“good-matchings”or “mismatchings”among institu-tionalformsareat thecoreofwell-tuned andfragile phasesof capitalism development.This is what has beenstudied by the (mainlyFrench)RegulationSchoolwhichidentifiedthesocalled RegimesofRegulation(seeBoyer,1988).

ThreemaindomainsoftheRegimesofRegulationareespecially relevantto studythe capitalistdynamics, namely:(i) the accu-mulationregimewhichentailstherelationsamongtechnological progress,incomedistributionandaggregatedemand,(ii)the insti-tutionalformswhichencompassthewage-labournexusandnature oftheState,and(iii)themodeofregulationcomprisesthe mech-anisms bywhich the former two domains evolve, develop and interact.Themodesofregulationcapturethespecificitiesofthe processofadjustmentsintheaccumulationpatternsandinthe coordinationamongdifferenttypesofactors.Suchdynamicsyields phasesof“smooth”coordination,mismatches,cyclesandcrises.

Themajorquestionis,then,thecoherenceandcompatibility of a given technicalsystemwith a patternof accumulation, itself definedby acomplex setofeconomic regularities and mechanismsaffectingcompetition,demand,thelabourmarket, creditandstateintervention.Themajorfindingisthefollowing: thereareseveraldifferentmodesofdevelopmentand regula-tionobservedinhistory–there isnosingleuniversalmode. [Boyer(1988)p.68]

The notion of mode of regulation disposes of the standard equilibrium-basedideaofcollectivecoordination.Itismadeofaset ofnorms,rules,behaviourscollectivelyconsistententailingsome distinctivefeatures:(i)decentraliseddecisionsaretakenwithout theneedfor each individual ororganization tounderstandthe wholesystem;(ii)itshapestheaccumulationregime;(iii)it repro-ducesasystemofsocialrelationships.

Therole of the industrialrelations, the mechanism of wage determination,therelativepowerofconflictingclasses,the indus-trialandlabourpoliciesarealsoimportantelementsinshaping thenational systemsof innovation (Nelson, 1993)and produc-tion.Non-marketinstitutionsarecrucialfortheunderstandingof theprocessofinnovativesearchandmoregenerallyofeconomic dynamics:

[...]thereisalotmoretotheinstitutionalstructureofmodern economiesthanfor-profitfirmsandmarkets.Firmsand mar-ketsdoplayaroleinalmostallarenasofeconomicactivity,but inmosttheysharethestagewithotherinstitutions.Inmany sectorsfirmsandmarketsclearlyarethedominantinstitutions, butinsometheyplayasubsidiaryrole.Nationalsecurity, edu-cation,criminaljusticeandpolicingaregoodexamples.Some sectors,likemedicalcare,areextremely“mixed”,andone can-notunderstandtheactivitygoingoninthem,orthewaysin

whichtheirstructure,waysofdoingthings,andperformance haveevolved,ifonepaysattentiononlytofirmsandmarkets. [Nelson(2016),p.18]

2.7. Methodology:whycomputersimulation

Giventheforegoinginterpretationofeconomicdynamics,the choiceoftherightinstrumentsofanalysisisofparamount impor-tance(inthefollowing,weshalljustaddressthemodellingdomain, even ifwellaware of thecomplementarity withstatistical and historical analyses). To overcome the straitjacket imposed by the standard tools, we advocate an extensive useof computer simulation, concerning both individual action and system-level interactions.

Itwouldappear,therefore,thatamodelofprocessisan essen-tialcomponentinanypositivetheoryofdecisionmakingthat purportstodescribetherealworld,andthattheneoclassical ambitionofavoidingthenecessityforsuchamodelis unrealiz-able. [Simon(1979),p.507]

Thechoiceofcomputersimulation modelsis notbychance: itallowstodescribetheeconomicagentsasbehavingaccording toproceduralroutines,whichareexecutedundertheformof algo-rithms,whereinsequenceofactionsandeventsindiscretetimecan beexplicitlyinsertedanddescribed,andheterogeneityisexplicitly modelled.Simulations,inthisrespect,arenotsimplyusedtomimic buttotesthypotheses.

Byconvertingempiricalevidenceaboutadecision-making pro-cessintoacomputerprogram,apathisopenedbothfortesting theadequacyoftheprogrammechanismsforexplainingthe data,andfordiscoveringthekeyfeaturesoftheprogramthat account,qualitatively,fortheinterestingandimportant char-acteristicsofitsbehavior. [Simon(1979),p.508]

Manycriticismshavebeenaddressedtocomputersimulation models,orastheyarenowadayslabelled, AgentBasedModels, particularly,(i)lackofrigorousspecificationsofthebehavioural equations;(ii)lackofparameterestimation;and(iii)lackof robust-ness.

ThefirstcritiqueinfactisrathersuperficialinsofarasABMsare amethodologywhichleavesroomofmanoeuvretothemodeller, allowingthechoiceamongdifferentspecificationsofbehavioural rules.Conversely,intheneoclassicalmodelsonlyoneruleis admis-sible,themaximizingbehaviour.However,thegreaterdiscipline ofthelatterisdeceiving.Themainstreammodellerisallowedfull freedomonthechoiceoftheargumentsofthefunction,the func-tionalformandtheconstraints,withoutanyexternalconsistency check(“whatdoactuallyagentsdothat?”).

Conversely, ABMsundertake a thorough externalconsistency checkonthebehaviouralrules,modesofinteractionandtimelineof events,whichdefinethechronologicalorderaccordingtowhichthe proceduresareundertaken.Thus,themodelisaskedtobe coher-entandascloseaspossibletoempiricaldata.Onlyabandoning thedeductive-normativeapproachofthemaximization endeav-our,themodellerisabletotestthevalidityofbehaviouralrules andalgorithmsvis-à-visthecorrespondingevidence.

Thesecondcritiqueconcernsthelackofparameterestimation. However,itisanothermisleadingpoint.AsBrock(1999) empha-sizes,regularitiesorscalinglawswhichareparticularwidespread ineconomicsare:

[...] ‘unconditionalobjects’,i.e. theyonlygiveproperties of stationarydistributions, e.g. ‘invariant measures’,and hence cannotsay much aboutthedynamics of thestochastic pro-cesswhichgeneratedthem.Toputitanotherway,theyhave littlepowertodiscriminateacrossbroadclassesofstochastic processes. [Brock(1999),p.410]

(7)

Buttheemergenceofthesescalinglaw,evenifdoesnotallow todiscriminateamongalternativestochasticprocessesallequally abletoreplicatethesameunconditionalobjects,areusefulto iden-tifyacceptableandnonacceptabletheories:

Nevertheless,ifarobustscalinglawappearsindata,thisdoes restricttheacceptableclassofconditionalpredictive distribu-tionssomewhat.Hence,Ishallarguethatscalinglawstudiescan beofuseineconomicscienceprovidedtheyarehandledand interpretedproperly[...]scalinglawscanhelptheory forma-tionbyprovisionofdisciplineontheshapeofthe‘invariant mea-sure’predictedbyacandidatetheory. [Brock(1999),p.411] Brock (1999) advocates both the analysis of unconditional objectsandtheestimationofconditionalones.ABMs,wesuggest, arethebestart-formsofaravailabletoundertakebothexercises. Suchmodelscanbeusedforboth thoughtexperimentsandalso aslaboratoriesforpolicyexperiments.Insteadofperformingthe usualmethodsofcausalitydetectionproposedbythetoolboxof econometrics,whatABMsallowistomodel“artificial”worlds.

WhenABMsareimplemented,theprotocolonefollowsimplies: (i)usingunconditionalobjectstorejecttheoriesunabletomatch statisticalregularities,(ii)performingpolicyexperimentswhich allowtounderstandthereactionofthesystemwhenhitbyboth external shocks, including policy changes, and, equally impor-tant,endogenoustechnological,organizationalones,andstructural changesaswell.

Theabilitytomatchstatisticalregularities,andparticularlylarge ensemble of statisticalregularities at the micro level, attempts to meet the external consistency criteria mentioned above. In accordancewithBrock(1999),onesdoesnotsimplytrytofind unconditionalobjects,buttobuildmodelsabletoprovideasound explanationofthestatisticalregularitiesatdifferentlevelsof obser-vation. Not all statistical objectsare equivalent litmus teststo accept/rejectatheory.Replicatingbusinesscycleco-movementsis difficultbutnottoodifficult.ObtainingParetodistributionsor simi-larlyskewedonesinwhatevermeasureofmicrointeractingagents isrelativelyeasy:infact,theyarealllikelyasignatureofcomplexity assuch.Gettingthetwotogetherismuchmoredifficult,andeven moreismatchingtheempiricalregularitiesconcerningtherelative magnitudeofthehighermomentsofdifferentvariables.

Finally,thelastcritiqueregardsthelackofrobustness,according towhichtheresultsinABMstendtobelocalandpotentiallyvalid onlyforasmallsetoftheparameterspace,withthevalueofthese parametersoftennotestimated.Notably,ABMsarenonlinear,high dimensional,complexmodelswherein,torepeat,inputsstrongly differfromoutputs.Conversely,standardneoclassicalmodelsare linearisedmodelsaroundthesteady-state.Hence,thetwo mod-ellingapproachesarepolesapartinthe“epistemologicalweight” theyattributetotheappropriatenessoftheunderlying assump-tionsaboutbehaviourandinteractionmechanismsvs.purported predictingabilities.InABMs,thevaluesoftheparametersareset ascloseaspossibletoempiricaldata,wheneveravailable,evenif admittedlyoftenwithoutanydirectestimationoftheir distribu-tions,astheyarenotgenerallyavailable.

Onthecontrary,neoclassicalmacroeconomicmodelslikeDSGE, beinglinearisedintheneighbourhoodoftheequilibriumvalues,to exhibitalowabilityingeneratingoutputswhicharedifferentfrom theinputsthemselves.Here,theepistemologicalstrategyisexactly theopposite.Thestructuralmodelisassumedtobeaxiomatically true,andonthegroundofsuch“truth”,thevalueoftheparameters arecalibratedinordertomatchtheempirics,bye.g.minimizingthe distancebetweentheseriesproducedbythemodelandthe empir-icalones.Followingacalibrationprocedure,themodellerdoesnot performanytestingontheinherentmodelstructure,butsimply imputesestimatedvaluesoftheparameters.

Inanutshell,whilestandardmacroeconomicmodelfocuson parameter estimations, ABMs entail a sort of theory corrobora-tion.Wheneveramodelisabletorobustlyreplicateanumberof stylisedfacts,withoutimposingspecificvaluesfortheparameters, themechanismsinsidethemodelitselfarereliableexplanationsof thefactsempiricallyobserved.

Oneopenchallengeaheadisthecomparabilitybetween high-dimensionalABMsandlow-dimensionalaggregatelawofmotions. Canwedramaticallyreducehigh-dimensionality,bothintermsof heterogeneityandintermsofvariablesandparameterspace,and stillcapturesomefundamentaldynamicsofthesystem?Orputting itananotherway,whatarethecomplementarity,ifany,between ABMsandgenuinelyclassicalnon-microfoundedmodelsuchthose inthetradition ofKaldor(1940),Goodwin(1951)and Pasinetti (1960)?

3. Domains

Thesearepartsofthebuildingblocksofa“grandevolutionary program”(discussedatgreaterlengthinDosiandWinter,2002)to putatworkwithrespecttotheformalizationoffourmaindomainof analyses:(i)technologies;(ii)organizations;(iii)corporate learn-ing,competitionandindustrialdynamics;and(iv)coordinationand growthfromthemicrotothemacroeconomicpatterns.

3.1. Technologies

Technologicalinnovation,paraphrasingLandes(1969),hasbeen andisacentraldriveroftheUnboundPrometheusfuelling eco-nomicgrowthatleastsincetheindustrialrevolution.Theclassics –andinparticularAdamSmith–werewellawareofit,butfor almosttwocenturiesthereafter,notmuchprogresshadbeenmade inourunderstandingofthewaysnewtechnicalknowledgeis gen-erated,andhowitsimpactworksthroughtheeconomy(KarlMarx andJosephSchumpeterstandoutasmajorexceptions).The impor-tanceof technologicalchangereappeared,almostby default,in RobertSolow’sgrowthanalysisinthe50’s,butitisonlyoverthe lasthalfcenturythatonehassystematicallystartedlookinginside theblackboxoftechnology(Rosenberg,1982).

Fundamentalcontributionstosuchade-blackboxinghavecome, first,fromtheanalysisoftheeconomicpropertiesofinformation assuch,including,asalreadymentioned,itsnon-rivalness; indi-visibility;andscalefreenessinitsuse;andthe(related)increasing returnspropertybothinitsutilizationanditsaccumulationover time.However,second,atleastequallyfundamentalcontributions havecomefromtheappreciationofthedifferencesbetween tech-nologicalknowledgeandsheerinformation–includingitsvarying degreesoftacitness,itsorganizationalembodiment,thedifficulties ofinter-andintra-organizationalreplication,anditscrucial depen-denceuponthecharacteristicsofparticulartechnologicalbases.

Intheopeningupofthetechnologicalblackbox,theaccountof technologiesintermsofpiecesofknowledge,theircombinations, andtheirchangeshastobecomplementedbyamoreoperational representationoftechnologyinaction.Theconception,designand completion of whatever artefact,generally involves(oftenvery long)sequencesofcognitiveandphysicalacts.Hence,itisusefulto thinkofatechnologyalsolikearecipeentailingadesignforafinal product,wheneverthereisafinalphysicalartefact,togetherwith asetofproceduresforachievingit.

AmajoradvancementandcontributionintheEconomicsof Inno-vationisthenotionthateachtechnologyneedstobeunderstoodas comprising(a)aspecificbodyofknowledgeandpractice–inthe formofprocessesforachievingparticularends–togetherwithan ensembleofrequiredartifacts,ontheinputside;and(b)quiteoften somesharednotionofadesignofadesiredoutputartefact.These elements,together,canbeusefullyconsideredasconstituentparts

(8)

ofatechnologicalparadigm(Dosi,1982,1988).Aparadigm embod-iesanoutlook,adefinitionoftherelevantproblemstobeaddressed andthepatternsofenquiryinordertoaddressthem.Itentails spe-cifictemplatesforthesolutiontoensemblesoftechno-economic problemsbasedonhighlyselectedprinciplesderivedfromnatural sciences,jointlywithspecificrulesaimedatacquiringrelatednew knowledge.Finally,technologicalparadigmsidentifytheoperative constraintsonprevailingbestpractice,andtheproblemsolving heuristicsdeemedpromisingforpushingbackthoseconstraints. Moreover,technologicalparadigmsbothprovideafocusforefforts toadvanceatechnologyandchannelthemalongdistinct techno-logicaltrajectories,withadvances(madebymanydifferentagents) proceedingover significantperiodsoftime in certainrelatively invariantdirections,inthespaceoftechno-economic character-isticsofartefactsandproductionprocesses.

Thetechnologiesasknowledgeandasrecipeperspectiveoffers anenormousprogressintheunderstandingofwhattechnological knowledgeisallaboutascomparedtotheblackboxingentailed bythetraditional representationoftechnologyasoutput=f(list of ingredients). Moreover,the recipe perspective offers promis-ingvenuesalsototheformalrepresentationofthedynamicsof problem-solvingproceduresinvolvedinanytechnologicalactivity, withinorganizationsinparticular.Insuchaproceduralview,the orientingfocusisnotimmediatelythelistofinputsandequipment usedtoproduce,say,asemiconductorofcertainproperties,but ratheritrestsinthedesignofthedevicesandtheproceduresused inthetransformationoftherawsiliconintoamicroprocessor.

Concerning technologicaladvance, modifications and refine-mentsof proceduresand designs arewherethe action is,while changesininput/outputrelations(theproductionfunctions)are inawaytheby-productofsuccessfulattemptstoachieveeffective proceduresanddesignswithcertainperformances,andtochange theminthedesireddirections.Thus,whatcomesundertheheading ofproductionfunctionsofwhateverkind,isbasicallyjustthe ex-postdescriptionofwhatappearsinthequantitypartoftherecipes. Notealsothat,dynamically,inmostcaseseffortstochangerecipes directlyentailchangesininputcharacteristicsandintensitiesand, conversely,attemptstosubstituteoneinputforanotherinvolve changesinproductionprocedures.Symmetrically,attemptsto sub-stitutethemoreexpensiveinputs–soeasywhenseenfromthe angleofsomestandard productionfunction– oftenrequirethe painstakingsearchofnewrecipesandeffectiveprocedures.

Grantedthat,aquestionwithcrucialramificationforanytheory ofproductionregardspreciselythemappingsbetween procedure-centredandinput/outputcentredrepresentationsoftechnologies. Supposeonehasametric intheinput/outputspace,and oneis alsoabletodevelop,a(albeitinevitablefuzzy)metricinthehigh dimensionalproblem-solvingspace.Next,howdothelattermap intotheformer?

Issuesofthesamekindregardtherelationshipbetweenchanges intherecipes,ontheonehand,andchangesintherelative intensi-tiesintheuseofthevariousinputs,ontheother.Dosmallchanges inprocedurescorrespondtosmallchangesininput/output rela-tions?And,viceversa,domajortechnologicalrevolutionsaffecting thewayofdoingthingsimplyalsomajorchangesinthe propor-tionsinwhichdifferentartefactsandtypesoflabourenterintothe recipesforwhateveroutput?Thatis,basically,whatarethe rela-tionshipsbetweenchanges intechnologicalprocedures andthe characteristicsoftechnologicaltrajectories,bothinthespacesof productcharacteristicsandofinputcoefficients?

3.2. Organizations

Agooddealofinnovationsaregeneratedwithincorporate orga-nizations,whiletechnologicalandorganizationalinnovationsare often intertwined. Thus, it is crucial to progress in the formal

explorationofthepropertiesofeconomicorganizationsseenas problem-solvingentities.Itispromisingtorepresenttheminterms ofexplicitsequencesofactivitiesandproceduresnestedinto spe-cificorganizationalarrangementsprescribingwhosendwhichsignal towhom,andwhodoeswhatandinwhichconsequence.

Notwithstanding promising inroads (see Marengo and Dosi, 2005;Dosietal.,2003;DosiandMarengo,2015),modelsstillfall shortofanexplicitformalaccountof(i)theemergenceand dynam-icsoforganizationalroutines;(ii)therelatedroleorganizational memory;andfinally,(iii)thelinksbetweenorganizational archi-tectures,knowledgedistributionandperformances.

Theknowledgeofanorganizationregards,first,itscognitive memory – the structure of beliefs, interpretative frameworks, codes,culturesbywhichtheorganizationinterpretsthestateof theenvironmentanditsown“internalstates”(LevittandMarch, 1988).Second,organizationalknowledgeincludesroutines– com-prisingstandardoperatingprocedures,rulesandotherpatterned actions. Both,cognitive modelsand operational repertoires are theoutcomesoflearningprocessesandthusevolveovertimein responsetoexperimentationandfeedbacksfromtheenvironment. However,theymightoftenbearquitehighdegreesofinertiaand path-dependentreproduction,asinfact,byitsnature, organiza-tional memoryreproducesover time what an organization has learnedthroughoutitshistory.

Signalsfromtheenvironments,aswellasfromotherpartsof theorganization,elicitparticularcognitiveresponses,conditional uponthecollectivementalmodelsthattheorganizationholds. Cog-nitivememorymapssignalsfromanotherwiseunknownworld intocognitivestates(thisyearthestateofthemarketissuchthatit willbeprofitabletoproduceX).Conversely,theoperational mem-oryelicitsoperatingroutinesinresponsetocognitivestates(“this yearweshouldproduceX”),internalstatesoftheorganization(“the machinesarereadytostartproducingpieceP”)andalso environ-mentalfeedbacks(“afterallXisnotsellingtoowell”).

Cognitiveandoperationalmemoriesentailanifthen struc-ture.Apromisingcandidatetomodelthemfindsitsrootsintothe formalismofClassifierSystems(Holland,1975,1986):apioneering applicationdevelopedinMarengo(1992)andsubsequent refine-mentsareinDosietal.(2017a,b).Onthegroundofsuchformal apparatusonecanfirstanalyzetheeffectsintermsofperformances ofdifferentdistributionsofknowledgeandoftherelated mem-oryelementswithintheorganization(e.g.whetherhierarchically versushorizontallydistributed,etc....)conditionalupondifferent characteristicsoftheenvironment.Second,thistypeofmodelsmay helptoexploretheconjecture–wellgroundedinseveral empir-icalstudies–thatamemorystructurewell“fit”foraparticular environmentmayturnouttobeperniciousunderdifferent techno-logicalormarketconditions(cf.amongothersTripsasandGavetti, 2000andBresnahanetal.,2011).Infact,inmanyrespects,much workhasstilltobedonein theexplorationof theoutcomesof themappings betweentypes ofknowledge, memory character-istics,organizationalarchitecturesandpatternsofenvironmental change.

3.3. Corporatelearning,competitionandindustrialevolution

Inmoderncapitalism,businessfirmsareacentrallocusofthe effortstoadvancetechnologies,developnewproductsandoperate newproductionprocesses.Thustheknowledgeandtheprocedures underlyingeachtechnology,discussedintheprevioussection,are toa goodextentembodiedin organizationalroutinesandother “quasigeneticactionpatterns”oforganizations(WinterinCohen etal.,1996).Indeed,anemergingcapability-basedtheoryofthe firm(cf.Dosietal.,2001,2008amongothers)placesthe “prim-itives” ofthe natureof businessfirms intheirproblem-solving features,thatistheirabilitiestoaddresspracticaland cognitive

(9)

problems,rangingfrom,say,theproductionofacartothe identi-ficationofamalaria-curingmolecules.

Theapproach,whichfindsitsrootsintheworksofH.Simon,J. March,A.ChandlerandS.Winter–fullyacknowledgingubiquitous formsofhumanboundedrationality,grosslyimperfectprocesses oflearninganddiversesocialdistributionsofcognitivelabour– attempts toidentifythedistinctive capabilitiesoforganizations as emergent fromtheirdistinctive ensembles of organizational routines.And,dynamically,theapproachtriestoaccountforthe processesbywhichorganizationalknowledgeisacquired, main-tained,augmentedandsometimeslost–partlyasaresultofthe dynamiccapabilitiesoforganizationthemselves(Teeceetal.,1997; Helfat,2007).

Idiosyncraticcapabilitiesand, dynamically,idiosyncratic pat-terns of learning by firms are the general rule. In turn, such persistentlyheterogeneousfirmsarenestedincompetitive envi-ronments, which shape their individual economic fate and, collectively,theevolutionoftheformsofindustrialorganization. Differencesinproductsandinprocessesofproduction–andasa consequencecostsandprices–arecentralfeaturesofthe com-petitive process in which firms are involved in different ways. LetuscallSchumpeteriancompetitiontheprocessthroughwhich heterogeneousfirms competeonthebasis of theproductsand servicesthey offerand obviously their prices, and getselected –withsomefirmsgrowing, somedeclining,somegoingout of business,somenewonesalwaysentering.Suchprocessesof com-petition andselection arecontinuouslyfuelledbytheactivities ofinnovation,adaptation,imitation byincumbentfirms andby entrants.Inturn,theprocessesofindustrialevolutionleaves statis-ticalfootprintsintermsofindustrialstructuresandfirmdynamics. Thankstomassiveinfusionsofmicro-dataoverthelast20years, onehasbeguntoidentifyafewrobuststatisticalproperties char-acterizingindustrial structures,theirchanges, and performance indicators.

Ingeneral,evolutionaryinterpretationsaregroundedontwo basicbuildingblocks.Thefirstisalearningpartwherein individ-ualagents(firms),massivelyboundedlyrationalbutalwaysable toinnovate, search for new techniquesand newproducts and thesecondisaselectionpartwherebymarketinteractions deter-mineex-postprofitabilities,survivalprobabilitiesandfirmratesof growth.Moreonthestructureofevolutionarymodelsofindustrial dynamicsinSilverbergetal.(1988),SilverbergandLehnert(1994), Metcalfe(1998)andDosietal.(1995,2017b).

The(idiosyncratic)learningpartofthedynamicsisoften repre-sentedasastochasticsearchforinnovationandimitationinthe neighbourhoodof theincumbenttechniquesof eachfirm. Con-versely,theselectionpartoftheprocessisbasicallycapturedby differentinstantiationsofsomereplicationdynamics.Thebottom lineis a relation betweensome corporate characters – that is, technological,organizational,orbehaviouraltraits–whichthe par-ticularinteractiveenvironmentfavours,ontheonehand,andthe rateofvariationofthefrequenciesinthecarriersofsuchcharacters intherelevantpopulationsontheother.

Onehasonlybeguntosystematicallylinkevolutionarymodels withthestylizedfactsofindustrialdynamicsdiscussedabove.Here thebigchallengeregardstheabilityofthemodelsofgenerating –andinthatsenseexplaining–therichensemblesofobserved empiricalregularities,boththosethataregeneric,holdingacross sectors,countriesandphasesoftheindustrylifecycles,andthose thatareregime-specific.Inthatthephenomenatobeexplained– rangingfromsizedistributionsandothermeasuresofindustrial structuressuchasconcentration,tothedistributionsofcorporate growthratesallthewaytothedeterminantsofgrowthitself– oughttobeunderstood,again,asemergentpropertiesstemming fromtheout-of-equilibriainteractionofheterogeneous,farfrom omniscient,butpotentiallyinnovative,agents.

In particular, to date, thegenerality of evolutionary models hasassumed some monotonicity in therelations between fun-damentaldeterminants ofcompetitiveness/revealedfitness, and subsequentrelativegrowth.However,theevidenceonthese selec-tiveprocessessuggeststhatselectionforcesareweakerthanthose theorised.In turn,this maywellbetheconsequenceofvarious formsofmarketimperfections –includinginformationalones– which,togetherwithendemicsatisfyingbehaviours,allowfirms characterizedbydiversedegreesofefficiencyandproductqualities toco-existwithouttoomuchrelativepressure.Onthemodelling sidesuchevidencedemandsanaccountofevolutionoccurringover multidimensionalfitnesslandscapes–explicitlycapturingthe mul-tidimensionaldifferencesinproductcharacteristics–rugged,thus allowingformultiplemetastablestates, butalsointertwinedby ampleflatareas–wherebyselectivepressuresarerelativelylow.

3.4. Frommicrotomacrocoordinationandgrowth

We have already discussed above that the interpretation of macroeconomic dynamics must have, in our view, micro-foundations explicitly resting on multiplicity of heterogeneous interactingagents. Granted that, there aretwo complementary modellingperspectives.

Inafirstone,whichwecouldcallcoordinationwithoutevolution, onemaystudytheconditionunderwhichcoordinationemerges, intertwinedbymajorphasechanges,inmarkets,andother inter-actingenvironments,whereinagentsinteractandadjustlocally. Thefundamentalsofsuchenvironmentsmightwellbestationary (hence,strictlyspeaking,noevolution),butthethreadof inter-actionsandadjustmentstypicallyyieldsnonlinearmacroscopic effectscharacterizedbydiversepatternsofcoordination(orlack ofit).Alotofworkhasbeendoneinthisperspective(forsurveys, seeTesfatsionandJudd,2006andLeBaronandTesfatsion,2008) offeringtheoreticaltalesonself-organizingpatterns.Still,oneis quitefarfromathoroughunderstandingofe.g.howmarketswork, conditionalontheirdifferentnetworkstructures,asconvincingly advocatedbyKirman(2011).

Together,letusstronglyurgetheinvestigationofcoordination withevolutiononthegroundofhigherdimensional, phenomeno-logically much richer Agent Based Models. Within a growing ensembleof ABMefforts(see FagioloandRoventini, 2016fora recentsurvey),theauthorsofthisnoteadvocaterefinementsand developmentsuponthefamilyof“SchumpetermeetingKeynes” models(Dosietal.,2010,2013,2015,2016,2017c).Theyclearly meetSolow(2008)’spleaformicroheterogeneity:amultiplicityof agentsinteractwithoutanyexantecommitmenttothereciprocal consistencyoftheiractions.

Thisfamilyof modelsbridges Keynesiantheoriesof demand generationandSchumpeteriantheoriesoftechnology-fuelled eco-nomicgrowth.Agentsalwaysfaceopportunitiesofinnovationsand imitation,whichtheytrytotapwithexpensivesearchefforts,under conditionsofgenuineuncertainty(sotheyareunabletoformany accurateexpectationsontherelationbetweensearchinvestment and probabilities of successful outcomes). Hence (endogenous) technological shocks (the innovations themselves) are unpre-dictableandidiosyncratic.

Thisfamilyofmodelsbuildsonevolutionaryroots,butisalsoin tunewithgenuineKeynesianinsights.Ittriestoexplorethe feed-backsbetweenthefactorsinfluencingaggregatedemandandthose drivingtechnologicalchange.By doingthat, itbegins tooffera unifiedframeworkjointlyaccountingforlong-termdynamicsand higherfrequenciesfluctuations. Themodel is“structural”in the sensethatitexplicitlybuildsonarepresentationofwhatagentsdo, howtheyadjust,interactandrespondtopolicychanges.Indeed, themodelhasalready provedtobeabletogeneratejointly,as emergentproperties,awide setof stylizedfactsregardingboth

(10)

micro/meso phenomenaand macro stylizedfacts.They include (i)endogenousgrowth;(ii)persistentfluctuations;(iii)recurrent involuntaryunemployment;(iv)pro-cyclicalconsumption, invest-ment,productivity,employmentandchangesininventories;(v) fat-taileddistributions ofaggregategrowthrates;togetherwith persistent asymmetries in productivity across firms; (vi) spiky investment patterns; (vii) skewed firm size distributions; (viii) fat-tailedfirmgrowthrates,and (ix)onthelabourmarket side Beveridge,Wage(orPhillips),andOkuncurves,(x)separationand hiringrates volatility, (xi)matching function,(xii)productivity, unemploymentandvacancyratesvolatility,(xiii)unemployment andinequalitycorrelation(cf.Dosietal.,2017c).Torepeat,the fore-goingrobuststatisticalregularitiesandrelativelystablerelations amongstaggregatevariablesdoindeedemergeoutofturbulent, disequilibrium,microeconomicinteractions. Assuch, themodel canbeusedalsoassortof“laboratory”forpolicyexperiments.We havebeguntodoit,showing,forexample,thecomplementarity betweenKeynesianandSchumpeterianpolicies.

4. Somechallengesahead,bywayofaconclusion

Inthesenoteswehavetriedtoofferanevolutionaryviewon, possibly,thetwomajorquestionswhichcutacrossthewholehistory ofeconomicsasadiscipline,namelythedriversofchangeandthe coordinatingpropertiesofasystemcomposedbymultiple inter-actingagents.Inmanyways,theyareasortofadvocacyof“back totheClassics”,especiallySmith,MalthusandMarx,albeitwith muchmoresophisticatedformalandcomputationalinstruments. Thebasicinterpretativeconjecturehereisthatthepropertieswe observestemfromthefactthatthecapitalisteconomiesarethefirst onesinhumanhistorywhichincessantly“changefromwithin”. Anditisthisveryfeaturewhichaccountsfortherelativelyorderly interactionswhichoneoftenobserves.

Thereisalotthatistheretobedoneonthetheoryside.And evenmoreso,ithastobedoneonsidesofstatisticsandof theory-informed,qualitative,historicalinterpretation,whatNelsonand Winter(1982)call“appreciativetheorizing”.Justtonamea few domains.

Some challenges were already there in the largely unfilled “SantaFecomplexityprogramme”(seetheintroductionbyPinesto Andersonetal.,1988).Forexample,firsthowdoagentsbehaveand learnin complexevolvingenvironments?Economics, especially over thelast half a century,hasput anoverwhelming empha-sisonexpectationsintheinterpretationofbehaviour,uniquein alldisciplines,whichmaturedbeyond“Aristotelian”finalcauses. Butthat,in turns, implies universally transparentpresents and futures,whichishardlyintunewithinnovation-ridden evolution-aryworlds.

Second,howdoesoneformallyaccountsforevolutionary pro-cesseswhereinthedimensionalityofthestate-spaceprogressively evolve?

Third,even shortofthat currenteconometrictechniquesare postulateduponuniqueequilibriumstatesshockedbyexogenous disturbances.But,whatiftherearee.g.non-lineardynamicswith multiplelocalattractors,persistentlyperturbedbyendogenously generatedshocks,howdoweaccountforthem?

Fourth,andwellbeyondtheSantaFeprogramme,whatisthe theoryofvalueandincome distributioninknowledgeintensive worlds,generallycharacterizedbyincreasingreturns?Note,inthis respect,thatifoneloosesconvexityinproductionplans,onelooses alsothelinkbetweenthetheoryofproductionandthetheoryof incomedistribution.Inourview,thisisjustagoodnews,butit posesaproblemalsoforclassical,cost-basedtheories:whenever thecostofreplicationisminor,likeinthecaseofthereproduction ofasoftwareoradrug,isitjustproportionaltothecostofengineers andscientistswhoundertooktheR&D?

Thelistisfarfrombeingexhaustive.Andthisismatchedby equallyimportant(orevenmoreimportant)interpretativeissues whichhavetodowiththecontemporarydynamicsofcapitalist economies.

Afirstoneconcernslabourmarket,wagesandemployment.The innovation-employment nexusdeservesoverridingattention.In thewakeofapotentialfourthIndustrialRevolution,ofadebate onproductivitydecline,“secularstagnation”andfuture robotiza-tion,researchaddressingtheeffectsonboththequantityandthe qualityofemploymentisneeded,aswellasthebalancebetween productandprocessinnovationintermsofemployment creation-destruction.

Asecond related oneis inequality.It isand willbethe core topic, together with unemployment, of the next many years. Eventhoughthepost-crisisperiodhasbeenmarkedbyan over-whelmingandblossomingliteratureoninequality,detailedstudies lookinginsidethetransformationatshop-floor, thewage deter-minationprocesses, theorganization oftheindustrial relations, the process of de-unionisation are partly missing and badly needed.Besidethat,what dowe knowaboutthepotentiallink betweenproductivityandwagedispersion,aspossible determin-ingmechanismscausingwage inequality,ascompared toother mechanismssuchasglobalizationandthefinancializationofthe economies?

Onthemodellingside,theSchumpetermeetingKeynesmodel leavesscopeformanypotentialavenuesforfurtherresearch:(i) theanalysisof theeffectof long-termversusshort-termlabour contractsonfirm productivity,exploringtheimpactofcontract durationontheprocessofworkersskillsaccumulation,and con-sequentlyonproductivity;(ii)anorth-southversiondirectedat studyingtheeffectofflowsofcapitalgoods,consumptiongoods andworkersamongtwocountries, aleadinganda laggingone, analysingtheemergenceofpatternsofproductspecialization vis-à-visdiversification,cost-competitivenessvis-à-vistechnological competitiveness, growthconvergence vis-à-vis divergence; (iii) theeffectofproductvis-à-visprocessinnovationintermsof cre-ation/destructionoflabourdemand.

Andlastbutnotleast,policyanalysesinvolveafundamental paradigmaticchange:thecentralconcernforpoliciesoughttoshift awayfromefficientallocationissues,tothe(imperfect)governance ofcoordination(Kirman,2011),and ofgenuinelyuncertain pro-cessesofchange.

Acknowledgements

ThisworkdrawsuponDosi(1984),DosiandWinter(2002),Dosi (2014)andDosiandVirgillito(2018).Wegratefullyacknowledge theparticipantsandtheorganizersof theworkshop“Economic Change and Evolution” held at theAcademia dei Lincei,10–11 November2014andthesupportbytheEuropeanUnion’sHorizon 2020researchandinnovationprogrammeundergrantagreement No.649186–ISIGrowth.

References

Abramovitz,M.,1956.ResourceandOutputTrendsintheUnitedStatesSince1870

,NBER,pp.1–23.

Anderson,P.W.,Arrow,K.,Pines,D.,1988.TheEconomyasaComplexEvolving

System.Addison-Wesley.

Arrow,K.,1996.Technicalinformationandindustrialstructure.Ind.Corp.Change

5(2),645–652.

Becker,G.,1962.Irrationalbehaviorandeconomictheory.J.Polit.Econ.,1–13.

Becker,G.,1976.Altruism,egoism,andgeneticfitness:economicsand

sociobiology.J.Econ.Lit.14(3),817–826.

Boyer,R.,1988.Technicalchangeandtheoryof‘Régulation’.In:Dosi,G.,Freeman,

C.,Nelson,R.,Silverberg,G.,Soete,L.(Eds.),TechnicalChangeandEconomic Theory.PinterPublisher,LondonandNewYork,pp.67–94.

(11)

Bresnahan,T.,Greenstein,S.,Henderson,R.,2011.Schumpeteriancompetitionand diseconomiesofscope:illustrationsfromthehistoriesofMicrosoftandIBM. In:Lerner,J.,Stern,S.(Eds.),TheRateandDirectionofInventiveActivity Revisited.UniversityofChicagoPress,pp.203–271.

Brock,W.,1999.Scalingineconomics:areader’sguide.Ind.Corp.Change8(3),

409–446.

Camazine,S.,etal.,2001.Self-organizationinBiologicalSystems.Princeton

UniversityPress.

Cohen,M.,Burkhart,R.,Dosi,G.,Egidi,M.,Marengo,L.,Warglien,M.,Winter,S.,

1996.Routinesandotherrecurringactionpatternsoforganizations:

contemporaryresearchissues.Ind.Corp.Change5(3),653–698.

David,P.,1985.ClioandtheeconomicsofQWERTY.Am.Econ.Rev.75(2),332–337.

DeMiguel,V.,Garlappi,L.,Uppal,R.,2009.Optimalversusnaivediversification:

howinefficientisthe1/Nportfoliostrategy?Rev.Financ.Stud.22(5), 1915–1953.

Dosi,G.,1982.Technologicalparadigmsandtechnologicaltrajectories:asuggested

interpretationofthedeterminantsanddirectionsoftechnicalchange.Res. Policy11(3),147–162.

Dosi,G.,1984.Technologyandconditionsofmacroeconomicdevelopment.In:

Freeman,C.(Ed.),Design,InnovationandLongCyclesinEconomic Development.DesignResearchPublications,London,pp.99–125.

Dosi,G.,1988.Sources,procedures,andmicroeconomiceffectsofinnovation.J.

Econ.Lit.26(3),1120–1171.

Dosi,G.,2014.EconomicCoordinationandDynamics:SomeElementsofan

AlternativeEvolutionaryParadigm,Introductionto“EconomicOrganization, IndustrialDynamicsandDevelopmentSelectedEssays”.EdwardElgar.

Dosi,G.,Orsenigo,L.,etal.,1988.Coordinationandtransformation:anoverviewof

structures,behavioursandchangeinevolutionaryenvironments.In:Dosi (Ed.),Tech.ChangeEcon.Theory,13–37.

Dosi,G.,Egidi,M.,1991.Substantiveandproceduraluncertainty.J.Evol.Econ.1

(2),145–168,ISSN:1432-1386.

Dosi,G.,Fagiolo,G.,Napoletano,M.,Roventini,A.,2013.Incomedistribution,credit

andfiscalpoliciesinanagent-basedKeynesianmodel.J.Econ.Dyn.Control37 (8),1598–1625.

Dosi,G.,Fagiolo,G.,Napoletano,M.,Roventini,A.,Treibich,T.,2015.Fiscaland

monetarypoliciesincomplexevolvingeconomies.J.Econ.Dyn.Control52, 166–189.

Dosi,G.,Fagiolo,G.,Roventini,A.,2010.SchumpetermeetingKeynes:a

policy-friendlymodelofendogenousgrowthandbusinesscycles.J.Econ.Dyn. Control34(9),1748–1767.

Dosi,G.,Faillo,M.,Marengo,L.,2008.Organizationalcapabilities,patternsof

knowledgeaccumulationandgovernancestructuresinbusinessfirms:an introduction.Organ.Stud.29(8–9),1165–1185.

Dosi,G.,Levinthal,D.A.,Marengo,L.,2003.Bridgingcontestedterrain:linking

incentive-basedandlearningperspectivesonorganizationalevolution.Ind. Corp.Change12(2),413–436.

Dosi,G.,Marengo,L.,2015.Thedynamicsoforganizationalstructuresand

performancesunderdivergingdistributionsofknowledgeanddifferentpower structures.J.Inst.Econ.11(03),535–559.

Dosi,G.,Marengo,L.,Paraskevopoulou,E.,Valente,M.A.,2017a.modelofcognitive

andoperationalmemoryoforganizationsinchangingworlds.Camb.J.Econ. 41(3),775–806.

Dosi,G.,Pereira,M.C.,Virgillito,M.E.,2017b.Thefootprintofevolutionary

processesoflearningandselectionuponthestatisticalpropertiesofindustrial dynamics.Ind.Corp.Change26(2),187–210.

Dosi,G.,Pereira,M.C.,Roventini,A.,Virgillito,M.E.,2017c.WhenmoreFlexibility

YieldsmoreFragility:theMflexibilityyieldsmorefragility:the microfoundationsofKeynesianAggregateUnemployment.J.Econ.Dyn. Control18,162–186.

Dosi,G.,Marsili,O.,Orsenigo,L.,Salvatore,R.,1995.Learning,marketselectionand

theevolutionofindustrialstructures.SmallBus.Econ.7(6),411–436.

Dosi,G.,Nelson,R.,Winter(eds.),S.,2001.TheNatureandDynamicsof

OrganizationalCapabilities.OUP,Oxford.

Dosi,G.,Pereira,M.C.,Roventini,A.,Virgillito,M.E.,2016.Theeffectsoflabour

marketreformsuponunemploymentandincomeinequalities:anagentbased model.In:LEMPapersSeries2016/27,LaboratoryofEconomicsand Management(LEM),Sant’AnnaSchoolofAdvancedStudies,Pisa,Italy.

DosiG.,VirgillitoM.E.,2018.The“Schumpeterian”andthe“Keynesian”Stiglitz:

Learning,CoordinationHurdlesandGrowthTrajectories,in“EconomicTheory

andPublicPolicies:JosephStiglitzandtheTeachingofEconomics.”M.Guzman

editor,ColumbiaUniversityPress,forthcoming.

Dosi,G.,Winter,S.,2002.Interpretingeconomicchange:evolution,structuresand

games.In:Augier,M.,March,J.(Eds.),TheEconomicofChoice,Changeand Organization.EssaysinMemoryofRichardM.Cyert.EdwardElgar, Cheltenham.

Fagiolo,G.,Roventini,A.,2016.MacroeconomicpolicyinDSGEandagent-based

modelsredux:newdevelopmentsandchallengesahead.In:LEMWorking Paper2016/17,LaboratoryofEconomicsandManagement(LEM),Sant’Anna SchoolofAdvancedStudiesmPisa,Italy.

Fogel,R.,1965.Thereunificationofeconomichistorywitheconomictheory.Am.

Econ.Rev.55(1/2),92–98.

Freeman,C.,Louc¸ã,F.,2001.AsTimeGoesBy:FromtheIndustrialRevolutionsto

theInformationRevolution.OUP,Oxford.

Gigerenzer,G.,Gaissmaier,W.,2011.Heuristicdecisionmaking.Annu.Rev.

Psychol.62,451–482.

Goodwin,R.,1951.Thenonlinearacceleratorandthepersistenceofbusiness

cycles.Econometrica19,1–17.

Grandmont,J.,1991.TransformationsoftheCommoditySpace,Behavioral

HeterogeneityandtheAggregationProblem.CowlesFoundationDiscussion Papers987.CowlesFoundationforResearchinEconomics,YaleUniversity.

Helfat,C.,2007.Stylizedfacts,empiricalresearchandtheorydevelopmentin

management.Strat.Org.5(2),185–192.

Hildenbrand,W.,1994.MarketDemand:TheoryandEmpiricalEvidence.Princeton

UniversityPress.

Holland,J.,1975.AdaptationinNaturalandArtificialSystems:AnIntroductory

AnalysiswithApplicationstoBiology,Control,andArtificialIntelligence. UniversityofMichiganPress.

Holland,J.,1986.Escapingbrittleness:thepossibilitiesofgeneralpurposelearning

algorithmsappliedtoparallelrule-basedsystem.Mach.Learn.,593–623.

Kahneman,D.,2002.MapsofBoundedRationality:APerspectiveonIntuitive

JudgmentandChoice.NobelLaureateAcceptanceSpeech.

Kaldor,N.,1940.Amodelofthetradecycle.Econ.J.50,78–92.

Kirman,A.,1992.Whomorwhatdoestherepresentativeindividualrepresent?J.

Econ.Perspect.6(2),117–136.

Kirman,A.,2011.ComplexEconomics.IndividualandCollectiveRationality.

Routledge,London.

Kirman,A.,2016.Complexityandeconomicpolicy:aparadigmshiftorachangein

perspective?AreviewessayonDavidColanderandRolandKupers’s complexityandtheartofpublicpolicy.J.Econ.Lit.54(2),534–572.

Landes,D.,1969.TheUnboundPrometheus:TechnologicalChangeandIndustrial

DevelopmentinWesternEuropefrom1750tothePresent.Cambridge UniversityPress,London.

Landes,D.,1994.Whatroomforaccidentinhistory?:explainingbigchangesby

smallevents.Econ.Hist.Rev.47(4),637–656.

Lane,D.,1993.Artificialworldsandeconomics,partI.J.Evol.Econ.3(2),

89–107.

LeBaron,B.,Tesfatsion,L.,2008.Modelingmacroeconomiesasopen-ended

dynamicsystemsofinteractingagents.Am.Econ.Rev.98(2),246–250.

Levitt,B.,March,J.,1988.Organizationallearning.Annu.Rev.Sociol.,319–340.

March,J.G.,1962.Thebusinessfirmasapoliticalcoalition.J.Politics24(04),

662–678.

Marengo,L.,1992.Coordinationandorganizationallearninginthefirm.J.Evol.

Econ.2(4),313–326.

Marengo,L.,Dosi,G.,2005.Divisionoflabor,organizationalcoordinationand

marketmechanismsincollectiveproblem-solving.J.Econ.Behav.Organ.58 (2),303–326.

Marshall,A.,1890.PrinciplesofEconomics.Macmillan,London.

Mas-Colell,A.,Whinston,M.,Green,J.,1995.MicroeconomicTheory,vol.1.Oxford

UniversityPress.

Metcalfe,J.S.,1998.EvolutionaryEconomicsandCreativeDestruction.Routledge.

Nelson,R.,1993.NationalInnovationSystems:AComparativeAnalysis.Oxford

UniversityPress.

Nelson,R.,2016.AnOverviewofModernEvolutionaryEconomics.mimeo.

Nelson,R.,Winter,S.,1982.AnEvolutionaryTheoryofEconomicChange.Harvard

UniversityPress,Harvard.

Nicolis,G.,Prigogine,I.,1977.Self-organizationinNonequilibriumSystems:From

DissipativeStructurestoOrderThroughFluctuations.Wiley&Sons,NewYork.

Pasinetti,L.,1960.Cyclicalfluctuationsandeconomicgrowth.OxfordEcon.Pap.

12,215–241.

Pasinetti,L.L.,1981.StructuralChangeandEconomicGrowth:ATheoreticalEssay

ontheDynamicsoftheWelfareNation.CambridgeUniversityPress, Cambridge.

Pianta,M.,2017.Theevolutionofeconomicstructures.Struct.ChangeEcon.Dyn.,

Thisissue.

Radner,R.,Stiglitz,J.,1984.Anonconcavityinthevalueofinformation.In:Boyer,

M.,Kihlstrom,R.(Eds.),BayesianModelsinEconomicTheory:Studiesin BayesianEconometrics,vol.5.ElsevierSciencePublications,pp.421–452.

Rosenberg,N.,1982.InsidetheBlackBox:TechnologyandEconomics.Cambridge

UniversityPress,London.

Rothschild,M.,Stiglitz,J.,1976.Equilibriumincompetitiveinsurancemarkets:an

essayontheeconomicsofimperfectinformation.Q.J.Econ.90(4),629–649.

Scazzieri,R.,2017.Evolutionarychangeandstructuraldynamics.Struct.Change

Econ.Dyn.,Thisissue.

Schumpeter,J.,1947.Capitalism,Socialism,andDemocracy.Harper&Brothers

Publishers,NewYorkandLondon.

Shaikh,A.,2016.Capitalism:Competition,Conflict,Crises.OxfordUniversityPress.

Silverberg,G.,Dosi,G.,Orsenigo,L.,1988.Innovation,diversityanddiffusion:a

self-organisationmodel.Econ.J.98(393),1032–1054.

Silverberg,G.,Lehnert,D.,1994.Growthfluctuationsinanevolutionarymodelof

creativedestruction.In:Silverberg,G.,Soete,L.(Eds.),TheEconomicsof GrowthandTechnicalChange:Technologies,Nations,Agents.EdwardElgar PublishingLtd,Aldershot,pp.74–108.

Silverberg,G.,Verspagen,B.,1994.Learning,innovationandeconomicgrowth:a

long-runmodelofindustrialdynamics.Ind.Corp.Change3(1),199–223.

Simon,H.,1969.TheScienceoftheArtificial.MITPress,MA.

Simon,H.,1979.Rationaldecisionmakinginbusinessorganizations.Am.Econ.

Rev.69(4),493–513.

Solow,R.,2008.Thestateofmacroeconomics.J.Econ.Perspect.22,243–246.

Teece,D.,Pisano,G.,Shuen,A.,1997.Dynamiccapabilitiesandstrategic

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

In this report, we described a case study of a patient admitted to our Internal Medicine Department for a bone marrow biopsy and myelogram due to a monoclonal peak observed by

The difference with the case of integral curves consists of the fact that the general plane section Z of an integral curve is made of points in uni- form position while in our case

(2) Second session: To simulate the slow and sporadic nature of infrastructure maintenance tasks, a second beacon deployment session took place over three months, during which

Con questo non improbabile vertiginoso incremento della sanzione viene meno anche la giustificazione della clausola di sussidiarietà iniziale, così come vengono a mancare

Rispetto a quest’ul- timo, il CB Terre Ducali si distingue per l’uso di ulteriori strumenti, come il bilancio preventivo, il piano strategico e altre analisi di dettaglio, che

Table 8: Assessment of the likelihood of pest freedom following evaluation of current risk mitigation measures against Phenacoccus solenopsis on Nerium oleander potted plants

Attenendosi alle indicazioni fornite dagli studiosi che concordano sul numero di manoscritti e testi a stampa registrati nel catalogo (1039 volumi di cui 33 ca. a stampa) e

Abrupt magnetic reconnection of the strong toroidal component launches brief relativistic outflow that pro- duce X-ray flares via internal collision-induced magnetic dissipation.