• Non ci sono risultati.

Party government : a rationalistic conception

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Party government : a rationalistic conception"

Copied!
78
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

EUROPEAN UNIVERSITY INSTITUTE, FLORENCE

DEPARTMENT OF POLITICAL AND SOCIAL SCIENCES

320

EUR

E U I

W O R K I N G

P A P E R No. 19

PARTY GOVERNMENT: A RATIONALISTIC

CONCEPTION.

by

RICHARD S. KATZ

SEPTEMBER 1982

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(2)

This paper is distributed for discussion

and critical comment and should not be

quoted or cited without prior

permission of the author

©

Richard S. Katz

Printed in Italy in September 1982

European University Institute

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(3)

Party Government: A Rationalistic Conception

Richard S. Katz

Department of Poli ti cal Science The Johns Hopkins University

Baltimore, Maryland 21218

That po li ti cal parties have been the central institutions of demo­ c r a t i c governments at l e a s t since the enfranchisement o f the working

c l a s s is w e ll known. D i s r a e l i wrote, " I b e l i e v e that without party

p a r l i a m e n t a r y g o v e r n m e n t i s i m p o s s i b l e " ( R os e, 197**: 1).

Schattschneider (19**2: 1) t e l l s us that "modern democracy is unthinkable save in terms o f party," whil e to S a r t o r i (1976: i x ) , " P a r t i e s are the central intermediate and intermediary s t ru c tu r es between soci ety and

government." Although as Rose ( 1969) points out, "operational control

of government" by parties i s often assumed rather than demonstrated, the li t er a ry theory (as Bagehot would have i t) or the dominant ideal-type or myth of democratic government in Western Europe has been the model of

party government. While party government has not been accepted quite so

readily as a description of government in the United States, i t has been

widely accepted as an i de a l there as w e ll ( K i r k pa t ri c k, 1950). With

varying degrees of sophistication and with more or fewer caveats, elabo­ rations, and qualifications, this has been true of p o li ti c al scientists,

j o u r n a l i s t s , and the general publi c. The character, as w e ll as the

success or failure of governments both in solving particular problems

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(4)

and in providing effective long term s t a bi li ty and leadership, is most commonly a tt r ib ut ed to the state o f the p a r t i e s and party system (Briggs, 1965; Allum, 1973).

Like other i d e a l i s a t i o n s of government — for example f i r s t that \ the king and then that the l e g i s l a t u r e ruled — the party government model is both descriptive and just if icat or y.1 At the descriptive level, the party government model assigns to poli ti cal parties a number of key

functions in the governing process, including m o bi li s at io n and

channeling o f support, formulation of a l t e r n a t i v e s , recruitment and replacement of leadership, and, when in power, implementation of policy

and control over its administration. At the normative level, the party

government model implies a particular view of democracy, in which the system i s made democratic by the e l e c t o r a l r o l e o f the p a r t i e s . Structures or i nd iv i du al s other than p a r t i e s and t he i r leaders could perform the functions attributed to parties and could contribute to the governing of society, but only parties offer the whole public a choice

among comprehensive and comprehensible a l t e r n a t i v e s . An e l e c t o r a l l y

v i c t o r i o u s party or c o a l i t i o n of p a r t i e s i s e n t i t l e d to control the decision making and implementing functions of government because i t has been authorised by the whole people to do so (Ranney, 1962).

The preceding paragraph ignores many thorny problems. Like other

idealisations, the party government model is oversimplified, and is not intended to be taken as a complete description of any particular govern­

ment. Its English origins are quite obvious, and both its descriptive

and i t s normative elements require modif icat ion before they can be

adapted to other political systems. Nonetheless, until recently i t was

generally accepted as a desirable ideal and also as a reasonably accu­

\

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(5)

r at e d e s c r i p t i o n o f the operation of European, i f not n e ce ss ar il y of American, democracy.

In recent years, however, widespread concern has been expressed g e n e r a l l y about the g o v e r n a b i l i t y o f i n d u s t r i a l or p o s t - i n d u s t r i a l s o c i e t i e s , and p a r t i c u l a r l y about the a b i l i t y o f pa r t i e s and party

governments to cope with contemporary problems ( C ro z i e r , 1975). A

variety of events, social changes, and results of academic research have called the party government model into question, both normatively and

e m p i r i c a l l y . Heightened awareness o f the independence of bureaucrats

and o f t h e i r r e l a t i o n s h i p s with organised i n t e r e s t s has raised the question of whether parties have been, or can be, in effective control

of policy. The broadening of government functions and the proliferation

o f governmental and quasi-governmental agencies indeed has raised the question of whether anyone can exercise comprehensive control. The rise o f social groupings and issues not reflected in existing party systems has introduced new s t r a i n s that threaten the s t a b i l i t y o f e x is t i n g institutions and raised doubts regarding the adequacy of representation by p a r t i e s ( I n g l e h a r t , 1977), while the e f f e c t i v e penetration o f organised groups into the governmental apparatus has challenged the

assumption that parties are necessary for representation. Moreover, the

suspicion that partisan bickering is responsible, at least in part, for the apparent incapacity of western governments to deal effectively with contemporary problems has raised doubts about the very desi rabi li ty of party government (Finer, 1975).

These doubts have contributed to a f e e l i n g that there i s a c r i s i s brought about by a lack of capacity on the part of the parties which is

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(6)

threatening the survival of party government and of democracy. This

suggestion r a i s e s questions c l u s t e r i n g in three main ca te gor ie s. Firstly, to what extent, and under what circumstances, do governments

conform to the party government model? Put somewhat infelicitously,

what i s the level of "party governmentness" of contemporary regimes, how is i t to be explained, and, projecting into the future, what changes in party governmentness should be expected on the basis of other poli ti cal ,

social, economic, and cultural developments? Secondly, how and under

what circumstances i s the l e v e l or organi sati on of party government r e l a t e d to a p o l i t i c a l system's capacity and potential for survival? Thirdly, is party government necessary for democracy or, less demand- ingly, is party government the only alternative to authoritarian, auto­

cratic, or di ctat or ial government? How much party government is there;

can i t survive; should one care?

These questions could be approached as historical descriptive prob­

lems to be addressed rel ati vely atheoretically. There is much s t i l l to

be said about the r o l e o f p a r t i e s in the governing of past and present

s o c i e t i e s at a purely d e s c r i p t i v e l e v e l . I f v a li d c ro s s- na t io na l

comparisons are to be made, i f events are to be explained, and especially i f an assessment of the consequences of potential or future events rather than only those that, have already occurred i s to be attempted, however, a more developed t h e o r e t i c a l framework w i l l be

necessary. In t hi s paper, I want to explore one possi ble such

framework. The remainder o f the paper i s divided into three main

sections. The f i r s t section is concerned with the choice of an overall

theoretical approach, or paradigm. The second section then addresses

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(7)

underlined in the l a s t paragraph. F i n a l l y , the purpose o f the third section is to relate these concepts to one another, drawing theoretical connections among them and suggesting hypotheses and a framework for

interpretation. Although examples w i l l be given when possible, since

this is primarily a theoretical paper rigorous tests of hypotheses w i l l be l e f t to future research.

Choice of Paradigm

Before any d e f i n i t i o n a l problems can be resolved or t h e o r e t i c a l p r op o si ti o ns advanced, one must choose the paradigm within which the

work w i l l take place. This involves deciding on the nature o f the

universe to be explained or studied — the "units" or "things" out o f which i t is made, the kinds of relationships that are important, and the

forces that might produce or modify those relationships. In effect, a

paradigm is a framework for the construction of an empirical theory and the choice o f a paradigm i s the choice o f the language in which the

theory w i l l be b u i l t and the research c ar ri ed out. Although research

based on one paradigm may be useful to work in another, a l l but the barest f a ct s (and sometimes those as w e l l , depending on op er ati onal

d e f i n i t i o n s o f concepts) r equi re t r a n s l a t i o n . For example, Fiorina

(1981) can make frequent use of the party identification variable from the Michigan surveys in his basically rati onal isti c account of American e l e c t o r a l choice, even c i t i n g f i g u r e s computed by those using other

approaches. His t h e o r e t i c a l d e f i n i t i o n of party identification, how­

ever, is quite different from theirs and so too is his interpretation of those figures.

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(8)

Paradigms are not f a l s i f i a b l e . They provide structures within which f a l s i f i a b l e empirical hypotheses may be formulated but have no

empi ri cal content themselves. Rather, a paradigm is judged by i t s

usefulness, that is by whether the theor ies advanced within i t are

verified and whether i t contributes to understanding. Ultimately, the

t es t o f a theory, and thus i n d i r e c t l y the measure of i t s parent para­

digm's usefulness, i s the " o b j e c t i v e " standard of accuracy. To date,

however, no social science theory has achieved a level of accuracy such

that it can stand on that ground alone. Thus, "generality, pl ausi bi li ty

and auxilliary implications" must remain important bases for judging theories and choosing paradigms (Fiorina, 1981: 190).

Unfortunately, one implication of this is that the choice of para­ digms i s l a r g e l y a matter o f t aste based on i nt u it io n. Moreover, the

paradigm that appears most useful for studying one class of phenomena may be d i f f e r e n t from that which appears most useful for another

(Kaplan, 1964: 258-326). I t i s not s u r p r i s i n g , then, that there has

been no consensus reached within po li ti cal science, or even within its

subfields. I f cumulative progress is to be made, however, this problem

must be resolved.

This paper i s not the place to debate the r e l a t i v e merits o f a l l the competing paradigms in p o l i t i c a l science, a task which has been

undertaken elsewhere (Barry, 1970; Holt and Richardson, 1970). Instead,

in t hi s section I only want to l ay out the basic elements o f the para­ digm I propose to adopt, that i s the r a t i o n a l i s t i c (in Barry's terms, the economic) paradigm.

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(9)

The basic unit for the rati onal isti c approach is the goal-oriented

rational actor. Goal-oriented actors are individuals who perceive that

they have goals and whose actions are motivated by a desire to achieve

those goals. People do not j u s t act, they act so as to bring about a

situation that they value more rather than one that they value less; i f there is behavior that cannot be regarded as purposive, it is inexplica­

bl e within the r a t i o n a l i s t i c framework. R a ti o n a l i t y i mpli es that in

attempting to further their goals, actors always try to maximise their

attainment with the minimum expenditure of resources. As Locke (1975,

section 131) put i t, "no rational creature can be supposed to change his condition with an intention to be worse."

Stopping here, one would not have said much, for i t seems apparent

that a l l behavior is rational. Indeed, i f a psychotic's withdrawal from

r e a l i t y lessens his pain, even that would be r a t i o n a l (Ke ll ey , 1957). Unless the goals being pursued are known or assumed, the rationalist can do l i t t l e beyond vacuous or jex post explanations o f the form "He did

what he did because he wanted to." Rationalistic work advances beyond

t hi s by sp ec if yi ng the ends to be pursued, but at t hi s point one

advances from the level of paradigm to that of specific theories. The

problem of what goals to consider with specific reference to a theory of party government is discussed below.

I t i s important to be c l e a r as to what this notion o f a g o a l -

oriented rational actor does not imply. Firstly, i t does not imply that

an individual's goals w i l l be mutually compatible in the sense of being

achievable simultaneously. There may be t r a d e - o f f s necessary in any

p a r t i c u l a r choice of action; one can with pe rf ec t r a t i o n a l i t y d es i r e ,

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(10)

both low taxes and a high l e v e l o f public expenditure for education. Indeed, the basi c assumption o f the most r a t i o n a l i s t i c o f th,e s oc i al sciences, economics, is that people simultaneously desire both guns and

butter in incompatible quantities. (See, however, Converse, 196M: 209.)

Secondly, it does not imply that an individual's goals are sensible as

seen by an outside observer. Some goals are simply matters o f t as t e;

that I consider something to be o b j e c t i o n a b l e , immoral, or s e l f ­

destructive does not preclude its pursuit by someone else. Other goals

are instrumental and thus based on real it y judgments. In this case, an

objective observer might decide that they were foolish or mistaken, but

t hi s r a i s e s the third point. Rational actors are not assumed to be

omniscient; indeed the costs of obtaining r el ia bl e information may be such that a rational individual would consider a blind guess to be more cost e f f e c t i v e than an informed judgment. Fourthly, r a t i o n a l actors need not make involved cost-benefit analyses before taking every action. Rules o f thumb and standard operating procedures are r a t i o n a l i f they have been proven satisfactory by experience, either real or vicarious. The search for an optimal st ra te gy may prove suboptimal i f excessive

search and decision costs are incurred. What is assumed is that indi­

viduals behave as _if they made cost-benefit analyses based on the goals they choose to pursue, with the resources available to them, and in the circumstances in which they find themselves.2

The r a t i o n a l i s t i c paradigm i s s e l f - c o n s c i o u s l y i n d i v i d u a l i s t i c . Neither groups nor or gani sati ons e x i s t as primary units within i t s

framework. Instead, they are viewed fundamentally as c o l l e c t i o n s of

i nd iv i d u a l s whose cooperation or cohesion must be explained (Olson,

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(11)

phenomena rather than individual actors; organisation is a strategy that may be pursued by some sets of individuals.

This does not mean that or g a n i s a ti o n s or s o c i a l groups may not

enter rationalistic theories for analytic simplicity. Theory building

and t es ti ng within the r a t i o n a l i s t i c paradigm proceeds by successive approximations. Simplifying assumptions regarding the nature o f the actors, the goals they pursue, the environment in which they operate, or the s t r a t e g i e s open to them are posit ed, and, on the b a s i s o f the consequent model, hypotheses are deduced concerning thei r behavior. These are tested and to the extent that predictions f a i l to f i t real ity

the model i s m o d i f i e d . In c o n s i d e r i n g the i n t e ra c t i on s among

organisations, i t may be productive i n i t i a l l y to regard them as unitary

actors. Downs' (1957) treatment o f p a r t i e s i s a c l a s s i c example o f

this. Although many suggestive conclusions could be derived from this

simplification, many anomolies remained. Others (e.g., Robertson, 1976)

later relaxed this assumption, obtaining a closer f i t with reality.

Organisations and i n s t i t u t i o n s may also play a r o l e in r a t i o n a l

theories as exogenous or situational variables. From the point o f view

of the individual(s) whose behavior is to be explained, an organisation

may appear to be a fixed structure like any other institution. Behavior

is decided on and takes place within an institutional structure. Since

t hi s p a r t i a l l y determines the r e s u l t s o f any p a r t i c u l a r pattern o f behavior, i t influences the l i k e l i h o o d that such behavior w i l l occur. For example, behavior on the part of a candidate that would be rewarded in a proportional representation system might be counterproductive, and

so less likely, in a plurality system. Cultural expectations similarly

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(12)

condition the expected responses from others and anticipation of those

responses w i l l influence the actor's i n i t i a l choice of behavior. Social

and economic variables may be considered in the same way.

Social structure may al so be rel evant to a r a t i o n a l i s t i c theory

through i t s i n f l u e n c e on the g o a l s o f i n d i v i d u a l s . Wh il e the

r a t i o n a l i s t i c paradigm does not recognise soc ia l c la s s e s as e n t i t i e s distinct from the individuals who comprise them, commonality of soc ia li ­

zing experiences and similarity of objective situations may lead members

of a social class to have similar interests and goals. Moreover, among

the values inculcated by these experiences may be a sub je c ti v e identification and consequent desire for group solidarity and conformity to perceived group norms. Again, however, c la ss s o l i d a r i t y and c la ss consciousness are seen not as natural but as needing explanation. S i m i l a r l y , while "working c l a s s Tories" may be exceptional in some countries, the r a t i o n a l i s t i c paradigm does not r e g a r d them as theoretical anomolies.

The rationalistic paradigm is a way of looking at the world and a

s t yl e o f explanation. In t hi s view, whatever the ultimate influence

exercised by social forces or institutional/organisational arrangements, the immediate cause of a poli ti cal event is always the conscious choice

of individual human beings. While social, economic, cultural, or poli­

t i c a l d i f f e r e n c e s may lead i n d i v i d u a l s who are otherwise s i m i l a r l y placed and pursuing the same goals to make different choices, i t is only through those choices that the influence of impersonal forces can be manifested.

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(13)

Conceptual Problems

Party

The consequences o f adopting a r a t i o n a l i s t i c approach begin to appear as soon as we think about p a r t i e s . In general terms, there are

two different ways in which parties may be viewed. The one most common

among adherents o f the various " s o c i o l o g i c a l " approaches, and the one often implicit in analyses of the functions of p o li ti c al parties or in a s s e r ti o ns that p a r t i e s do, or ought to do, c ert ain things, as w e l l as in comparisons o f the behavior or " g e s t a l t " o f d i f f e r e n t types o f

p a r t i e s , i s to see each party as an organic en ti ty . In t h i s view,

parties seek to control the government and, in this attempt, may either conflict or cooperate with other organisations or structures in society such as mass media, bureaucracy, i n t e r e s t groups, business f i r ms , and the military.

From the rati onal isti c perspective, however, party must be seen as

a "they" rather than as an " i t . " Moreover, once one t r i e s to develop a

rigorous theory or to o p e r a t i o n a l i s e the concepts necessary for empi­ rical research, the corporate view of party leads to great d i f f i c u l t i e s .

Two may be mentioned here. The f i r s t concerns the coherence of party.

I f party i s to be regarded as a whole, i t ought to be p o s s i b l e , for

example, to identify i ts goals. As constant conflict and debate within

the British Labour party makes clear, however, i t is not always a simple task to i d e n t i f y a party's a u t h o r i t a t i v e voice so as to i d e n t i f y i t s

goals. Similarly, in f actional ised p a r t i e s the deci sion of c o n st it u ­

t i o n a l l y authorised party organs may not bind the party's constituent

parts.3 Far from rescuing the corporate view, attempts to regard each

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(14)

party as a microcosmic political system simply underline the inadequacy of the original conceptualisation.

This i s underscored by the second problem which i s in many ways

even more d i f f i c u l t . The corporate view must assume p a r t i e s to have

d i s t i n c t b o u n d a r i e s t hat se t them a p a r t from other structures

( E l d er s ve ld , 1964: 1). In f act , there i s obviously a deep interpene­

tration of these supposedly rival and autonomous power sources. What,

for example, is one to make of the situation in which a church or trade union controls policy by creating a "captive" po li ti cal party to do its

bidding? Although the British Labour party has grown more autonomous

than i t was originally, the trade unions s t i l l dominate i ts conference.

Is it a separate institution or an arm of the trade union movement? I f

the bishops d i c ta t e po li cy to a Christi an democratic party, i s the church simply a successful pressure group, or is the party an arm of the

church? And what of the converse case, when a party creates ancillary

organisations that behave like other interest groups? Is the Italian

CGIL the Communist party in another form or an autonomous and

p o t e n t i a l l y r i v a l group? In either case, t o t a l autonomy and t o ta l

subservience are both overstatements; there are both connections and differences. This reality is easily lost in viewing party as a distinct organism.

The alternative view is to deny the independent existential basis

o f party, as well as o f other groups. Instead, party i s seen as an

or gani sa ti on o f , or structured pattern of interactions among, indivi­

duals in pursuit of their own goals. Rather than being an independent

actor, party is an instrument or conduit or basis of influence used by

i n d i v i d u a l s . In this case, one properly speaks o f functions being

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(15)

performed within or through p o l i t i c a l p a r t i e s rather than by them. E s p e c i a l l y , one is alerted to the p o s s i b i l i t y that "party functions" might be performed elsewhere or not at a l l , even while or g an is a ti o ns calling themselves parties exist.

This h i gh li g ht s a c l e a r problem with f unctional d e f i n i t i o n s o f

parties. I f parties are defined by their functions, party nonfeasance

becomes a logical impossibility. Likewise, i t becomes impossible for

the defining functions of parties to be performed by any other institu­

tion since i t would thereby become a party. One may, of course, s t i l l

refer to the functions of p ol it ic al parties in the sense of "things done by individuals through the mechanism of party" and be concerned with the importance o f those things and o f having them done by p a r t i e s for the

po li ti cal system.1* As Smith (1982) observes, however, " I t is one thing

to provide a functional 'check-list,' but quite another to imply that a party, a party system or an arrangement o f party government e x i s t s in

order to 'perform' certain functions. The approach readily lends i t s e l f

to distortion. It implies some kind of over-arching system rationality

without ever being c alle d upon to demonstrate i t s presence....Without n e c e s s a r i l y committing i t s e l f , the f unct ional ordering a d d i t i o n a l l y takes on a s t a t i c emphasis, tending to look for a fixed r e l a t i o n s h i p

between structure and function." While the r a t i o n a l i s t i c approach

assumes that indivi dual actors are r a t i o n a l , i t makes no assumptions about the " r a t i o n a l i t y of the system," and indeed research has shown that i nd iv idu al r a t i o n a l i t y may lead to c o l l e c t i v e i r r a t i o n a l i t y (Hardin, 1968).

What kind of an organisation i s a party and how is i t distinguished

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(16)

from other structured patterns of interaction? The answer l i e s in the functions o f p o l i t i c a l p a r t i e s , not for the p o l i t i c a l system as in a

functional a na ly si s , but for those who use them. P o l i t i c a l p a r t i e s

developed in the nineteenth century with the rise of mass suffrage and

regularised political participation. They were created to support and

assist their organisers who were already in government (in the case of p a r t i e s o f i ntraparl iamentary o r i g i n ) or who wished to get into

government ( p a r t i e s o f extr apar li ament ar y o r i g i n ) . 5 They replaced

combinations o f members o f parliament who supported or opposed the government o f the day on the b a s i s o f t he i r personal i n t e r e s t s or preferences, the i n t e r e s t s or preferences of t he ir sponsors, or in

return for p a r t i c u l a r i s t i c rewards. Party represents a s t ra t e g y by

which support in the mass publi c may be curried and converted into

p o li ti c al power in an electorally oriented democratic society. The key

change was ultimate dependence on popular e l e c t i o n , and the ce nt ral d i s t i n c t i o n between pa r t i e s and other groups i s that they contest e l e c t i o n s and r e l y on t he i r success in e le c ti o ns for t he i r claim to legitimate participation in government.

Left at t h i s , personal campaign or gan isa ti on s would q u a l i f y as p o l i t i c a l p a r t i e s , and to a l i m i t e d e x t e n t and e s p e c i a l l y in

p r e s i d e n t i a l systems they do. P r e s i d e n t i a l systems requi re s pe c i a l

treatment because personal and party victory in a presidential election are synonymous; whichever person/party wins that one e le c ti o n wins

control o f the executive branch o f government.^ In parliamentary

systems — and in the le gi s la t iv e branch of presidential systems — the r e a l prize comes not from a s i n g l e candidate's v ic to r y, but from the

formation of a l e g i s l a t i v e majori ty. P o l i t i c a l pa r ti e s are further

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(17)

di st ing uishe d by t h e i r cooperative seeking of m a j o r i t i e s , and the_ concomitant right and obligation collectively to govern and to be held responsible for governing.

Fundamentally, parties represent to the voters alternative teams of rulers and to the members of those teams a device for mobilising support

to compete with the members of other teams. The basis o f this competi­

tion may be programmatic or i d e o l o g i c a l , but i t need not be. In par­

ticular, conservative parties may have no concrete program, only a broad philosophy and a b e l i e f in t he ir own a b i l i t y to r ul e in the national

interest (Beer, 1969: 99; Amery, 1953: 4-31). Other parties may have no

a r t i c u l a t e d goal beyond supporting a p a r t i c u l a r leader. The party

politician is committed, or acts as i f he were committed, to a coopera­ t i v e quest for power, not j u s t a personal quest for o f f i c e , while the party voter is voting for a team in addition to a particular candidate.

This conception o f party has obvious roots in the r es ponsi ble

p a r t i e s doct rine. In that notion, p a r t i e s are the l i n k between the

publi c as a whole and the government as a whole. For pa r t i e s to serve this function, voters must be able to treat them as collective entities. Only i f parties behave cohesively in the discharge of public of fice, and only i f their candidates are prepared to stand or f a l l as a team on the basis of the party's collective record in of f ic e and proposals for the future can vo t er s, whose e l e c t o r a l vocabulary is necessarily limited, have a chance to speak e f f e c t i v e l y ( L o w e ll , 1913: 67-69; Schatt-

schneider, 1942: 52). Party is defined here with at least an eye toward

this theory.

In admitting this, i t becomes necessary to consider three further

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(18)

questions. The f i r s t concerns the nature of party unity and indirectly the question of internal party "democracy" in the case of parties with

mass memberships. The "party democrats" have seen p a r t i e s as "huge

a s s oc i at io n s o f partisan vot ers, " and have i nsisted that they be internally democratic (Schattschneider, 1942: 54; Kirkpatrick, 1950: 22-

23). This has n a t u r a l l y raised some complaints that i n t e rn a l party

competition is incompatible with collective action in government. While

t h i s point may be v a l i d e m p i r i c a l l y , i t i s t h e o r e t i c a l l y p o s s i b l e to argue that int ernal party democracy requi res not only that there be competition within the party but also that a l l party people, including the losers of this internal competition, behave cohesively v i s - a - v i s the

external world in support of the victorious position. It is only this

point that is required by partyness. Whatever the internal organisation

or rules of the party, and whatever the level of consensus or dissensus among party people, in thei r r e l a t i o n s with nonparty i n d i v i d u a l s and groups, those following a party strategy of poli ti cal action must behave as a team.

The second question concerns the nature of the competition among

those teams. The responsible parties theory of democracy generally is

associated with the requirement that pa r t i e s present c l e a r and d i s t i n c t i v e pl atforms, s p e l l i n g out the p o l i c i e s they w i l l f o l l o w in

o f f i c e . Because the party that wins an el ec ti on (assuming a s i n g l e

party does achieve a majority) can be trusted to put its manifesto into p r a c t i c e , t hi s a l l o w s voters to exercise prospective control over

policy. Parties might, however, compete on the basis of their records

in o f f i c e , in which case the control exercised by voters would be r e t r o s p e c t i v e , and might be based either on p o l i c i e s or on outcomes

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(19)

( F i o r i n a , 1981: chap. 1). Indeed in the l a s t case, the choice of the voters — and correspondingly the competition among the parties — may be based on confidence in a particular team of leaders without necessary regard for the policies they have pursued in the past or would pursue in

the future. While these differences are important, they do not bear on

a party's claim to that name. A l l that i s required i s c o l l e c t i v e

accountability, made possible by the expectation of collective action in o f f i c e .

The third question concerns party membership. Who i s the party?

Most broadly, one could argue that a party con si s ts o f everyone who

votes for or sympathises with it. Demands for internal democracy based

on an i n s t i t u t i o n l i k e the American d i r e c t primary i m p l i c i t l y assume

t hi s view. Except for reaching an e l e c t o r a l de c is io n, i t i s hard to

imagine such an " o r g a ni s at i on ” taking any sort o f c o l l e c t i v e action; "members" make no promises of l o y a l t y and may not have even to admit their membership publicly; there can be no regular communication among members, only from le ade rs to f o l l o w e r s ; no sanctions can be imposed

agai nst deviants. A more r e s t r i c t e d view would be to look only at

formal members in the European card-carrying sense, but this implies a

mass membership party. Even t h i s , however, confuses supporters with

p a r t i c i p a n t s . Although the i n d i v i d u a l i s t i c o r ie n t a t i o n renders the

whole problem of only marginal concern, the view taken here is that the leadership is the party, and when party is discussed as an actor, it is

to the collective leadership that reference is meant. This is the only

group small enough and in s u f f i c i e n t l y constant communication that consciously concerted action i s po ssi bl e. This i s not to deny the

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(20)

importance of mass membership in some parties, and of the decisions of

supporters for a l l parties. Members may take many policy decisions —

although always subject to the i n t e rp r et a ti o n o f party l eader s. They

may also choose the leaders. Nonetheless, they are no more "the party"

than c i t i z e n s are "the government" in repre se nt ati ve democracies. F i n a l l y , as suggested above, mass membership i s not necessary f or a party at a l l .

The three requirements or defining characteristics of "partyness" thus are: Dcohesive team behavior; 2)orientation toward winning control over the t otal it y of political power exercised by elected o f f i c i a l s and

those appointed by elected o f f i c i a l s ; and 3) claiming legitimacy on the

basis of electoral success. Organisations with many different structural

forms could satisfy these criteria and properly be called parties. On

the other hand, organi sati ons that c a l l themselves p a r t i e s might not. For example, clandestine groups that do not contest elections — even i f only because they are l eg all y barred from doing so — would not qualify

as p o l i t i c a l parties as the term is meant here.? More generally, since

organisations can vary in the degree to which they satisfy each of these requirements, t hi s implies t h a t " p ar ty n es s " ought to be regarded as a v a r i a b l e with a range o f values, i f not n e ce s s a r i l y as a continuum,

rather than as a dichotomy. In these terms, the B r i t i s h Conservative

party i s more p a r t y - l i k e than the I t a l i a n Christian Democracy, whil e both are more party-like than the American Republicans, who are in turn more party-like than the American Prohibition party.

Party Government

In defining party governmemt, one is again confronted with a choice

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(21)

between a dichotomy and a range. There has been some tendency to regard party government as a category into which a system either does or does not f i t . For example, Mintzel and Schmitt (1981a; see also 1982b) say "Party government is that form of societal conflict regulation in which a p l u r a l i t y o f d emoc ra ti cal l y organised p o l i t i c a l pa r t i e s play a r e l a t i v e l y dominant r o l e both in the socio-political mediation sphere and in the actual process o f p o l i t i c a l decision-making (government

sphere)." Similarly, Sjttblom (1981) suggests with a Venn diagram that

party government is a class, although he also proposes nested subclasses that might be taken as successively closer approximations of an ideal type.

I f one i s i nterested in the causes, consequences, and future o f

party government, however, t hi s approach i s of l i t t l e help. Leaving

aside Mintzel and Schmitt's questionable insistence on democratically organised parties, presumably a reference to their internal arrangements rather than to their commitment to democracy in the wider governmental sphere, i f party government i s a category, i t e vi de nt ly includes a l l modern Western democracies with the p o s si b le exception o f the United

States. I f this is so, then the concept is of no empirical value, since

the corresponding operational variable w i l l have no variance. Moreover,

i f party government means government through parties and partyness can vary, then party governmentness must be able to take on a range o f values as well.

Party government i s an a b st ra cti on of European parliamentary

democracy in the era of mass suffrage. Although most clearly based on

academic interpretations of British practice, the party government model i s an i n t e l l e c t u a l construct whose l o g i c i s f ar more coherent than i s

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(22)

the actual operation of any r ea l party governments. In h i s t o r i c a l terms, the party government model represents the adaptation o f the i n s t i t u t i o n s o f bourgeois p a r l i a m e n t a r y democracy ( w h i ch were adaptations of the institutions of royal government) to democracies with e l e c t o r a t e s numbering in the m i l l i o n s rather than the thousands. For democratic theory, the party government model makes government accountable to the general public by entrusting i t to i n d i v i d u a l s o r g a n i s e d i n t o p a r t i e s t hat owe t h e i r p o s i t i o n s to e l e c t o r a l

approbation. More concretely, party government involves at least four

conditions.

Firstly, a l l major governmental decisions must be taken by people chosen in e le c t i o n s conducted along party l i n e s , or by i n d i v i d u a l s

appointed by and responsible to such people. It is not necessary that

p a r t i e s compete on the b asi s o f a l t e r n a t i v e poli cy proposals, but whatever p o l i c i e s are made must be made by i n d i v i d u a l s who owe t he i r a ut hor it y e it he r d i r e c t l y or i n d i r e c t l y to the e l e c t o r a l success o f

their parties. Recognising that a permanent bureaucracy is an essential

f eat ure o f a l l modern governments, t hi s condition i s v i o l at ed to the extent that bureaucrats exercise independent policy making authority. It is similarly violated whenever rule making power is turned over to individuals who cannot be removed by elected of ficials® or to functional boards whose members owe their positi ons to t he ir r o l e s in i n t e r e s t groups or the like rather than to party appointment or election.

Secondly, policy must be decided within the governing party, when there is a "monocolor" government, or by negotiation among parties when

there i s a c o a l i t i o n . Not only must po li cy be made by elected

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(23)

o f f i c i a l s , a condition met for example by the American Congress, i t must also be made-along party l i n e s , 'so that each party may be held

collectively accountable for "its" position. This condition is not met

by the Congress. Similarly, cross-party negotiations among factions, as

occurs in Italy, also violates this condition.

Thirdly, the highest o f f i c i a l s (e.g., cabinet mi ni st ers and

especially the prime minister) must be selected within their parties and

be r es ponsi ble to the people through t he i r p a r t i e s . P osi ti ons in

government must f low from support within the party rather than party

positi ons f lowi ng from e l e c t o r a l success. For example, the B r i t i s h

practice whereby the l e a d e r o f the ma jor ity party in the House o f Commons becomes prime minister is consistent with the party government model while the American usage of declaring the winner of enough primary elections to be nominated for president, or of enough popular votes to be elected president, t he re fo re to be the l eader o f his party i s not. That B r i t i s h party l e a d e r s often remain as l e a de r s even a f t e r t he ir p a r ti e s are defeated but are u n l i k e l y to survive a s u b s t an t ia l intraparty defection even i f they formally win the "vote of confidence," while a presidential candidate's "party leadership" can withstand major int ernal de fe cti ons but not e l e c t o r a l d e f e at , i s i n d i c a t i v e o f t hi s

d i s t i n c t i o n . The French case i s more complicated, but c los er to the

party government model than to the American model. Mitterand became the

presidential candidate of the Socialist party because he was the party's leader (although clearly his presidential appeal was a condition for his

r i s e to party l e a d e r s h i p ) ; he remained party l eader even a f t e r his

defeat in the 197M election. Giscard was si mil arly party leader f i r s t

and president second. His leadership of the larger French right while

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(24)

he was president, however, was more in the American mold.

Fourthly, party-based leaders must be able ef fectively to control

the bureaucracy and other public or semi -publ ic agencies. Party

domination o f the elected branches o f government must carry with i t

control over the entire governmental apparatus. Although bureaucrats

are never p o l i ti c al l y irrelevant, the party must be able to coordinate and direct their work effectively.

A number of observations must be made regarding this definition of

party government. Firstly, it represents an ideal type, rather like but

in contrast to Dahl's (1971) i deal type o f polyarchy. As such, i t

represents an extreme that may be approximated but is neither realised

nor r e a l i s a b l e in the ultimate sense. It i s also a multidimensional

concept. Thus a p a r t i c u l a r system may c l o s e l y approximate the i d e a l

type in one respect but not in another. For example, while the

partyness of American congressional-presidential relations is extremely low in comparison to its British parliamentary-cabinet counterpart, the partyness of the American bureaucracy i s higher than that o f the

British. Similarly, even within a single po li ti cal system the degree to

which many dimensions of the ideal are approximated may vary from one policy area, time, or set of circumstances to another.

Secondly, party government i s not a complete d e s cr ip t io n o f government or i n s t i t u t i o n s . While perhaps more c l e a r l y derived from consideration of adversarial or majoritarian systems in which elections choose between rival and alternating sets of leaders and policies, the basi c l o g i c o f the model i s equally a p p l i c a b l e to c on soci ati onal or

c o a l i t i o n a l systems.9 while perhaps more d i f f i c u l t to achieve in

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(25)

p r e s i d e n t i a l and/or federal systems, party government i s l o g i c a l l y compatible with these i n s t i t u t i o n a l arrangements as w e ll as with parliamentary and unitary systems.

Together, these two observations imply that many d i f f e r e n t

approximations o f the party government model are po s si b le . Assuming

that a single quantitative measure of party government were devised, it would combine several dimensions with the result that two systems could achieve the same "party government score" while standing quite

di ff er entl y on the individual dimensions. Whether the dimensions that

comprise the o v e r a l l concept o f party government are s u f f i c i e n t l y coherent that this does not occur, or whether the dimensions o f the o v e r a l l concept must be considered s e pa r at el y , i s a question for empirical research.

In the same way, s i m i l a r "par ty government scores" might be

achieved by countries with very d i f f e r e n t party systems. Two party

competitive systems, systems with a l t e r n a t i n g c o a l i t i o n s , systems dominated by a single party or coalition with a semipermanent opposition (so long as i t i s permitted to contest e l e c t i o n s f r e e l y ) , and systems

with grand c o a l i t i o n s a l l are po t en ti a l party governments. Whether

similar levels of party government are produced by similar conditions and whether they lead to similar consequences in these di ff er ing systems also must be resolved empirically.

Finally, this definition of party government is intended to distin­

guish party government from other forms o f government. I t speaks,

t h e r e f o r e , to the "partyness o f government" as a c h a r a c t e r i s t i c o f formal institutions and indicates the proportion of formal governmental

power exercised in accordance with the party government model. To the

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(26)

extent that its conditions are met, what formal government there is w i l l

be party government. There is no guarantee, however, that there w i l l be

any effective formal government at a ll . While the "authoritative all o­

cation of values" goes on in a l l societies — even those with no " p o li t ­ ical" institutions — the government of the party government model may be more or less relevant to this process.

This observation has two consequences for the definition of party government. F i r s t l y , i t means that those conditions which de fi ne or promote government in general must be appended to those s p e c i f i c a l l y

relating to party government. Secondly, adding these considerations to

the d e f i n i t i o n o f party government underlines a d i s t i n c t i o n between partyness as a c h a r a c t e r i s t i c of the formal government apparatus and

party governmentness as a s oc i al c h a r a c t e r i s t i c . For example, in a

l a i s s e z - f a i r e economy, high partyness of government would s t i l l leave p a r t i e s in a r e l a t i v e l y marginal position in the a u t h o r i t a t i v e

a l l o c a t i o n o f economic values. Correspondingly, i f the power of

government grew while the party politicians' relative a b i l i t y to control it shrank, parties might become absolutely more important in the overall a l l o c a t i o n o f values even while the l e v e l of partyness o f government

decli ned. Party governmentness i s then a c h a r a c t e r i s t i c o f the

" he rr s c h a ft s o r g a n i s a t i o n" of the wider s oci ety, and i nd ic at es the proportion of a l l social power exercised by parties within the framework of the party government model.

Capacity

Looking at the chronic economic problems of many western countries, or s t i l l more at the collapse of democratic regimes in the interwar era,

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

(27)

there is a strong temptation of attribute these d i f f i c u l t i e s to a lack

o f capacity on the part o f the government or p a r t i e s . There i s an

element o f truth to thi s. Assuming that the governments o f the

contemporary west want to "solve” their economic problems, and assuming that the democratic regimes o f Germany, I t a l y , and Spain "wanted" to survive, their failure to do so certainly indicates a lack of capacity. This, however, i s a tautology, not an explanation; i f f a i l u r e i s the d e f i n e r o f low capacity, low capacity cannot be the explanation of

f a i l u r e .

Moreover, in many cases i t is not c l e a r that f a i l u r e as defined

from outside real ly is an indicator of low capacity. To listen to the

r h e t or i c o f some l e f t wing p o l i t i c i a n s , one might wonder whether bourgeois parties real ly do want to reduce unemployment; after a l l , i t

keeps wages low and workers docile. Similarly, inflation is beneficial

to some groups, at l e a s t in the short run. Beyond the d e b a t a b i l i t y o f

what a solution to many problems is, the cost of a solution in terms of personal or organisational goals may be so high that politicians choose

not to solve the problem. In Thurow's ( 1980: 44) view, for example,

Richard Nixon could have stemmed American i n f l a t i o n in 1972 had he pe rs i st ed with recessi onary p o l i c i e s ; he believed that to do so, however, would cost him the 1972 election and so he chose to change his

po li cy . Objective f a i l u r e thus may be the r e s u l t o f lack o f w i l l or

lack of foresight rather than lack of ability. Finally, some problems

may have no sol ut ions. I f poverty i s r e l a t i v e rather than a bsol ut e,

then the poor w i l l always be with us.

This suggests that "problem solution capacity" actually consists of

four d i s t i n c t , or s e m i d i s t i n c t , elements. The f i r s t element i s the

©

The

Author(s).

European

University

Institute.

produced

by

the

EUI

Library

in

2020.

Available

Open

Access

on

Cadmus,

European

University

Institute

Research

Repository.

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

Já tinha quarenta anos que ouvia as vozes, havia se separado e depois de seis meses já não ouvia mais as vozes negativas, com uma estratégia de controle e uma participação no grupo de

The study aims are to evaluate the analytical performance and the clinical results of the chemiluminescent Access AccuTnI + 3 immunoassay for the determination of cardiac troponin

The short run effects of financial constraints (FCs) on the expected growth rate of firms and their long-term implications on the evolution of the firm size distribution have

Both the emission intensities of the buried Trp48 (Figure 4 a) and of the exposed Trp129 in the R129W protein (Figure 4 b) and in the W48A / R129W double mutant (Figure 4 c)

In order to evaluate whether 3-HAA could bind NCOA7 in cells physiologically expressing high levels of the nuclear coactivator, MLN cells were treated with Ncoa7-specific or

Studies were included if they compared levels of disability, pain, quality of life, the rate of fusion and complications, and the need for reoperation in patients treated with

Here we show that genes induced by both ROS and anoxia include some encoding HSPs and ROS-related transcription factors (TFs) and we propose that the expression of those genes