• Non ci sono risultati.

Feminism

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Feminism"

Copied!
21
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

Feminism

(2)

Introduc/on

We  can  dis9nguish  between  three  concerns  of  feminism:  

1.  Feminism  tracks  the  domina9on  of  women  in  a  male-­‐dominated  

society.  

2.  Feminism  engages  cri9cally  with  the  liberal  public-­‐private  dis9nc9on.  

3.  Feminism,  as  a  theory  of  difference  and  not  equality,  proposes  an  

alterna9ve  concep9on  of  jus9ce.  

Let's  have  a  look  at  these  three  different,  though  complementary,  

outlooks  in  feminism.      

(3)

1.  The  difference  approach

•  Un9l  well  into  this  century,  restric9ons  on  women's  civil  and  poli9cal  rights   were  said  to  be  jus9fied  by  nature:  Women  are  naturally  unsuited  for  

poli9cal  and  economic  ac9vi9es  outside  the  home.  

•  Contemporary  theorists  view  women  as  'free  and  equal  beings'  and  liberal   democracies  have  progressively  adopted  an9-­‐discrimina9on  statutes  that   guarantee  the  equality  of  rights  in  the  poli9cal  sphere  and  the  equality  of   opportunity  in  the  economic  sphere.  Women  have  equal  access  to  

educa9on,  employment,  poli9cal  office,  etc..  

•  The  extension  of  rights  and  a  sex-­‐blind  or  gender-­‐neutral  society  is   supposed  to  solve  the  problems  women  face.              

•  MacKinnon  calls  this  the  'difference  approach'  to  sexual  discrimina9on,  for   it  views  as  discriminatory  unequal  treatment  that  cannot  be  jus9fied  by   reference  to  some  sexual  difference  (p.  379).  

(4)

1.  The  dominance  approach

•  Yet,  the  difference  approach  is  problema9c.  MacKinnon  writes  that  "sex  equality  law  has   been  u%erly  ineffec9ve  at  geZng  women  what  we  need  and  are  socially  prevented  from   having  on  the  basis  of  a  condi9on  of  birth:  a  chance  at  produc9ve  lives  of  reasonable  

physical  security,  self-­‐expression,  individua9on,  and  minimal  respect  and  dignity"  (p.   378).  Sex  equality  does  not  prevent  women  from  the  'second  shi]'  or  'double  day',  with   women  being  dispropor9onately  represented  in  low-­‐paying,  part-­‐9me  work,  which  

makes  them  economically  dependent.  

•  The  problem  isn't  any  longer  old-­‐fashioned  chauvinism.  The  problem  is  that  jobs  are  

designed  for  people  who  are  not  primary  caretaker  of  children  and  can  afford  compe9ng   and  working  10h  a  day.  Women  need  not  be  discriminated  against.  The  fact  that  they   have  to  and  perhaps  also  want  to  take  care  of  children,  auto-­‐excludes  them  from  most   a%rac9ve  and  well-­‐paid  posi9ons  and  relegates  women  to  the  low-­‐paid  sector.      

•  The  problem  is  that  society  is  sexist  in  its  very  founda9ons.  McKinnon  therefore  

proposes  the  'dominance  approach'  to  sex  equality  that  seeks  to  ensure  not  only  the   absence  of  discrimina9on,  but  equal  power  of  women  and  men  in  defining  society.          

(5)

1.  The  dominance  approach  and  theories  of  

jus/ce

•  Many  feminists  argue  that  theories  of  jus9ce  interpret  equality  in  ways  that  are  incapable  of   recognizing  women's  subordina9on.  Therefore  we  should  give  up  interpre9ng  jus9ce  in  terms  of   equality.  Yet,  the  dominance  approach  is  also  an  interpreta9on  of  equality,  though  more  complex   than  formal  equality.  

•  Is  the  dominance  approach  consistent  with  mainstream  theories  of  jus9ce?  Communitarianism   and  libertarianism  could  reject  its  premises.  First  claims  that  social  roles  are  given,  second  insists   on  the  employers'  freedom  to  design  jobs  however  they  see  fit.    

•  Can  liberal  theories  adopt  the  dominance  approach?  MacKinnon  argues  that  the  dominance  

approach  goes  beyond  liberalism,  but  Kymlicka  believes  that  liberalism  can  accommodate  much,   if  not  all  feminist  concerns.  Formal  equality  is  not  enough  and  the  different,  mostly  hidden  ways   women  are  discriminated  against  and  dominated  in  poli9cs,  society  and  the  market  can  be  

countered,  if,  as  Moller  Okin  argues,  "Rawls's  contractors  would  insist  on  a  more  complete  a%ack   on  the  system  of  gender  differen9a9on,  elimina9ng  both  the  unequal  domes9c  division  of  labor   and  sexual  objec9fica9on"  (p.  385).  

•  Yet,  the  dominance  approach  might  require  liberals  to  revise  the  private-­‐public  dis9nc9on  and   the  rela9onship  between  jus9ce  and  care.    

(6)

2.  Liberalism  and  the  public-­‐private  

dis/nc/on

• 

According  to  liberalism,  jus9ce  refers  to  the  'public'  realm,  whereas  

familial  rela9onships  are  private  and  lie  outside  of  the  state's  

competences.  Therefore  theories  of  jus9ce  con9nue  to  ignore  

rela9ons  within  the  family.  

• 

Yet,  as  Carole  Pateman  writes,  the  "dichotomy  between  the  public  

and  the  private  is,  ul9mately,  what  feminism  is  all  about"  (p.  387).    

• 

There  are  two  concep9ons  of  the  public-­‐private  dis9nc9on  in  

liberalism:  (1)  the  dis9nc9on  between  the  poli9cal  and  the  social  and  

(2)  the  dis9nc9on  between  the  social  and  the  personal.  Neither  

(7)

2.  (1.)  State  and  civil  society

•  This  dis9nc9on  equates  the  public  with  the  state,  and  the  private  with  civil   society.  And  liberalism  valorizes  civil  society,  since  it  is  the  best  expression   of  our  freedom.  

•  One  might  think  that  the  family  is  part  of  the  civil  society,  yet  liberalism   conceptualizes  civil  society  in  abstrac9on  of  the  family,  as  a  realm  that   contains  only  adult  men.  

•  Why  do  liberals  not  ensure  that  domes9c  life  is  organized  along  principles   of  equality  and  consent?  One  reason  is  that  liberals  inherited  the  

tradi9onal  assump9ons  concerning  the  women's  natural  role.      

•  Yet,  the  liberal  state-­‐society  dis9nc9on  is  in  any  sense  based  upon   tradi9onal  gender  roles.  

(8)

2.  (1.)  State  and  civil  society  (  cont.)

Are  there  feminist  grounds  for  rejec9ng  the  liberal  state-­‐society  dis9nc9on,  once  it   is  no  longer  based  upon  the  dis9nc9on  between  female  domes9c  sphere  and  the   male  public  sphere?  There  are  some  points  of  dispute:  

•  Feminists  might  endorse  stronger  policies  of  interven9on  in  civil  society  in  order   to  encourage  the  maintenance  of  certain  social  9es,  including  familial  ones.  

•  Feminists  may  not  share  the  liberal  faith  that  freedom  of  speech  and  the  press   will  counteract  prejudice  and  stereotypes  and  so  may  endorse  stronger  

government  policies  to  fight  demeaning  cultural  images  of  women.  

•  Feminists  believe  that  ac9ve  state  policies  are  needed  to  challenge  the  problem   of  'adap9ve  preferences'  (the  contented  housewife),  while  liberals  tend  to  think   that  individual  rights  and  distribu9ve  jus9ce  are  going  to  do  away  with  the  

(9)

2.  (2.)  The  personal  and  the  social:  the  right  

to  privacy  -­‐  the  problem  

•  This  second  dis9nc9on,  going  back  to  Roman9cism,  separates  the  personal   from  the  public,  whereas  the  'public'  includes  both  state  and  civil  society.   Individuality  is  threatened  not  only  by  coercion,  but  also  by  the  pressure  of   social  expecta9ons  and  conformism.  This  second  dis9nc9on  is  discussed   under  the  heading  of  a  'right  to  privacy'.  

•  Yet,  the  right  to  privacy  is  interpreted  by  the  US  Supreme  Court  in  terms  of   the  privacy  of  the  family.  As  a  result,  it  has  immunized  the  family  from  

reforms  designed  to  protect  women's  interests  -­‐  for  example,  state  

interven9on  that  would  protect  women  against  domes9c  violence  and   marital  rape,  or  empower  women  to  sue  for  non-­‐support,  or  officially   recognize  the  value  of  domes9c  labor.  This  way,  the  right  to  privacy   reinforces  the  division  between  public  and  private.    

(10)

2.  (2.)  The  personal  and  the  social:  the  right  

to  privacy  -­‐  the  solu/on  

• 

In  order  to  protect  women's  interests,  the  right  to  privacy  must  be  

extended  to  individuals  and  not  to  families.  This  becomes  possible  

through  the  detachment  of  privacy  from  patriarchal  ideas  of  family  

autonomy.  Accordingly,  "state  ac9on  may  be  needed  within  the  

domes9c  sphere  to  protect  privacy  and  prevent  abuse"  and  

"guarantee  women  (or  children)  a  sphere  for  personal  retreat  from  

the  presence  of  others,  or  from  the  pressure  to  conform  to  others'  

expecta9ons"  (p.  398).  

• 

In  conclusion,  the  "feminist  cri9ques  of  privacy  leave  the  liberal  

concep9ons  of  privacy  of  private  choice  very  much  alive"  (p.  398).    

(11)

3.  The  ethic  of  care

•  Women  are  since  always  supposed  to  have  different  modes  of  thought  and   feeling  -­‐  more  intui9ve,  emo9onal,  par9cularis9c  disposi9ons.  And  in  fact,   women's  supposed  different  nature  is  one  reason  for  their  discrimina9on.  

•  There  is  a  strand  in  contemporary  feminism,  however,  that  argues  that  we  should   take  seriously  women's  different  morality.  It  is  a  mode  of  moral  reasoning  and  a   source  of  moral  insight  that  is  ra9onal  and  public  in  scope.    

•  These  feminist  theories  go  back  to  Carol  Gilligan  (In  a  Different  Voice,  1982)  who   discovers  that  women  reason  in  terms  of  interpersonal  rela9onships  and  context,   whereas  men  tend  to  impersonal,  abstract  and  universal  reasoning  in  terms  of   principles.  She  labels  women's  morality  as  'ethic  of  care'  and  men's  morality  as   'ethic  of  jus9ce'.  

•  There  is  some  controversy  if  this  different  voice  really  exists  and,  if  it  does,  

whether  it  is  significantly  correlated  with  gender.  Another  ques9on  is  if  a  care-­‐ based  approach  to  poli9cal  ques9ons  competes  with  jus9ce.    

(12)

3.  Ethic  of  jus/ce  vs.  Ethic  of  care

The  debate  concerns  the  following  issues:  

1.  moral  capaci9es:  learning  moral  principles  (jus9ce)  versus  

developing  moral  disposi9ons  (care)  

2.  moral  reasoning:  solving  problems  by  seeking  principles  that  have  

universal  applicability  (jus9ce)  versus  seeking  responses  that  are  

appropriate  to  the  par9cular  case  (care)  

3.  moral  concepts:  a%ending  to  rights  and  fairness  (jus9ce)  versus  

a%ending  to  responsibili9es  and  rela9onships  (care).  

(13)

3.  (1.)  Moral  capaci/es

•  Also  for  theories  of  jus9ce  moral  disposi9ons  are  important.  Even  if  jus9ce   involves  applying  abstract  principles,  people  do  develop  a  'sense  of  jus9ce'   only  if  they  learn  a  broad  range  of  moral  capaci9es.  

•  Most  jus9ce  theorists  neglect  the  development  of  the  affec9ve  capaci9es,   since  they  suppose  that  the  sense  of  jus9ce  and  the  sense  of  care  is  

learned  within  the  family.  

•  Yet,  as  Okin  points  out,  if  the  family  is  itself  gendered  and  children  learn   within  the  family  about  despo9sm  and  exploita9on  rather  than  equality   and  reciprocity,  then  the  whole  structure  of  moral  development  is  built   upon  uncertain  grounds.      

•  Therefore,  jus9ce  theorists  have  to  accept  the  care  theorists  emphasis  on   moral  disposi9ons  and  pay  more  a%en9on  to  the  jus9ce  of  the  family.      

(14)

3.  (2.)  Moral  Reasoning

Jus9ce  theorists  are  right  in  being  universalist  (insis9ng  on  principles)  rather   than  situa9onist  (responding  to  the  complexity  of  a  given  situa9on).  Why?   •  Not  all  contextual  features  are  relevant  to  moral  decisions.  We  need  to  

dis9nguish  salient  and  irrelevant  features  of  moral  situa9ons.  

•  Moral  demands  may  conflict  and  we  need  principles  to  solve  this  conflict.     •  It  is  not  clear  that  we  always  should  try  to  accommodate  conflic9ng  

demands.  

•  We  have  limited  resources  for  caring.  We  need  moral  guidelines  for   ordering  our  priori9es.  

(15)

3.  (3.)  Moral  concepts

The  dis9nc9on  between  'rights  and  fairness'  and  'responsibili9es  and  

rela9onships'  can  be  construed  in  at  least  three  ways:  

1.  universally  versus  concern  for  par9cular  rela9onships  

2.  respect  for  common  humanity  versus  respect  for  dis9nct  

individuality  

(16)

3.  (3.1.)  Universality  versus  preserving  

rela/onships

For  care  theorists,  morality  requires  responding  to  percep9on  of  need  within   the  context  of  rela9onships  and  not  the  categorical  impera9ve.    

This  is  problema9c,  since  the  care  ethics  risks  to  exclude  the  most  needy,   since  they  are  most  likely  outside  the  exis9ng  web  of  rela9onships.  

Therefore,  some  care  theorists  expand  the  web  of  rela9onships  to  include  all   human  beings.  This  is  problema9c:  

•  We  lose  the  dis9nc9on  between  the  par9cularity  of  rela9onship  and  the   generality  of  principle.    

•  Moreover,  imposing  impar9ality,  a%achment  loses  its  moral  relevance.   •  The  ethics  of  care  leaves  also  unclear  how  conflicts  of  interests  between  

(17)

3.  (3.2.)  Respect  for  humanity  and  respect  for  

individuality

Jus9ce  neglects  people's  dis9nct  individuality.  It  is  concerned  with  the   'generalized  other'  rather  than  the  'concrete  other'.  Care  responds  to   concrete  differences  rather  than  our  abstract  humanity.  

This  contrast  seems  overdrawn  in  both  direc9ons:  

•  The  ethic  of  care,  once  universalized,  also  appeals  to  common  humanity.     •  Theories  of  jus9ce  are  not  limited  to  respect  for  the  generalized  

other.According  to  Okin,  Rawls'  theory  of  jus9ce  does  not  depend  upon  a   disembedded  and  disembodied  being  but  requires  that  "as  moral  subjects,   we  consider  the  iden99es,  aims  and  a%achments  of  every  other  person  (...)   as  of  equal  concern  with  our  own.  We  must  develop  considerable  

capaci9es  for  empathy  and  powers  of  communica9ng  with  others  about   what  different  human  lives  are  like"  (p.  408).    

(18)

3.  (3.3.)  Accep/ng  responsibility  and  claiming  

rights

• 

Jus9ce  is  concerned  with  rights,  whereas  care  with  accep9ng  

responsibili9es.  For  Gilligan,  care  requires  concern  for  welfare,  

whereas  rights  are  essen9ally  self-­‐protec9ve  and  selfish.  

Yet,  except  for  libertarians,  theories  of  jus9ce  recognize  posi9ve  du9es  

concerning  the  welfare  of  others.  

• 

Is  there  a  difference  in  the  kind  of  responsibility  each  ethic  insists  

upon?    

For  care  ethics  whatever  subjec9vely-­‐felt  hurt  is  immoral  whether  or  

not  it  is  fair.    

(19)

3.  (3.3.)  Jus/ce  as  fairness:  the  challenge

Why  do  jus9ce  theorists  limit  our  responsibility  for  others  to  the  claims  

of  fairness?  

• 

Some  interests  remain  my  own  responsibility,  otherwise  we  reward  

irresponsibility.  We  are  responsible  agents.  

• 

Taking  into  account  subjec9ve  hurts  can  hide  oppression  (see  

exploita9ve  and  oppressive  rela9ons).  Oppressors'  subjec9ve  hurts  

have  no  moral  weight,  since  they  arise  from  unfair  and  selfish  

expecta9ons.  

• 

Using  subjec9ve  hurt  as  the  basis  of  moral  claims  imposes  too  great  a  

responsibility  for  others.  There  seems  to  be  no  limits  to  our  

(20)

3.  (3.3.)  The  place  for  an  ethic  of  care

Care  theorists  counter  that  we  need  to  dis9nguish  a  'self-­‐less'  concep9on  of   caring  from  a  'self-­‐inclusive'  concep9on  of  caring.  This  is  what  dis9nguishes  a   'feminist'  ethic  of  care  from  a  'feminine'  ethic  of  self-­‐sacrifice.  

Yet,  how  much  autonomy  can  we  claim  for  ourselves  and  how  much  

reciprocity  can  we  demand  from  others,  without  neglec9ng  the  subjec9ve   hurt  of  others?  

Care  theorists  do  not  resolve  this  ques9on  by  developing  a  system  of  

abstract  rules.  Yet,  autonomy  requires  that  responsibili9es  are  predictable   and  codified  in  advance.    

However,  the  assump9on  that  subjec9ve  hurts  give  rise  to  moral  claims  is   plausible  if  applied  to  our  rela9ons  with  dependants  (children).  A  baby  is  not   responsible  for  its  needs  and  cannot  be  expected  to  a%end  its  parent's  

(21)

3.  (3.3.)  Care  as  a  maNer  of  jus/ce

• 

The  distribu9on  of  care  is  a  ma%er  of  jus9ce.  Care  is  a  moral  

constraint  on  every  life-­‐plan.  Prac9ces  of  care  should  be  seen  as  an  

obliga9on  of  ci9zenship.  

• 

Ways  need  to  be  found  that  integrate  public  life  and  paren9ng.  

Theories  of  jus9ce  too  o]en  ignore  that  we  are  adults  who  are  care-­‐

givers  for  dependants.  

• 

The  real  ques9on  is  if  we  can  meet  our  responsibili9es  for  dependent  

others  without  giving  up  the  more  robust  picture  of  autonomy,  in  

terms  of  seZng  of  personal  goals  and  the  commitment  to  personal  

projects.    

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

al problema del trasporto in una nube con clumps aleatori, e dopo alcuni richiami sulla teoria generale dei problemi di evoluzione (capitolo 2), nei capitoli 3 e 4 rivolgeremo la

Il Museo Archeologico Regionale “Paolo Orsi” di Siracusa, nel maggio del 2014, si è arricchito di un nuovo settore espositivo per- manente relativo alla città tardoantica, un

In questa prospettiva occorre rimarcare che – in rapporto con le tematiche emerse nel convegno del 2009 – docenti e ricercatori attivi presso il Centro hanno partecipato al

sette, Coscetto dal Colle popolano, uomo di grande valore e ardire, il quale era stato capo di popolo in Pisa a cacciare Uguiccione da la Faggiola, e poi a uccidere quegli della

While the existing literature primarily looks at neoliberal feminism as a hegemonic discourse that reflects and legitimizes unequal power relations in

We derive the accretion rate from the mass of a spherical shell whose inner radius is 2R 200 , whose thickness changes with redshift, and whose infall velocity is assumed to be equal

This previously read: WHO Collaborating Centre for Metabolic Bone Diseases, University of Sheffield Medical School, Sheffield, UK.. Should read: Centre for Metabolic Bone

Ibriste, un misterioso popolo di Sciti nomadi. Questa prima parte della profezia nel Prometeo è stata considerata interpolata, mentre la sezione qui esaminata è concorde- mente