• Non ci sono risultati.

Beyond Subjective and Objective in Statistics

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Beyond Subjective and Objective in Statistics"

Copied!
3
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

24 July 2021

AperTO - Archivio Istituzionale Open Access dell'Università di Torino

Original Citation:

Beyond Subjective and Objective in Statistics

Published version: DOI:10.1111/rssa.12276 Terms of use:

Open Access

(Article begins on next page)

Anyone can freely access the full text of works made available as "Open Access". Works made available under a Creative Commons license can be used according to the terms and conditions of said license. Use of all other works requires consent of the right holder (author or publisher) if not exempted from copyright protection by the applicable law. Availability:

This is the author's manuscript

(2)

Comment on “Beyond Subjective and Objective in

Statistics”

Jan Sprenger∗ April 8, 2017

I would like to congratulate Professors Gelman and Hennig with a paper that bridges philosophical and statistical inquiry in an impressive way. They deserve credit for taking subjective judgment out of the closet, and for showing how it improves sta-tistical reasoning when applied in an transparent, open-minded, and empirically in-formed fashion. This connects well to philosophical analysis of the social dimension of objectivity: transparency about subjective assumptions facilitates scientific discussion, opens up avenues for mutual criticism, and promotes the formation of a balanced, informed judgment (Longino, 1990; Harding, 1991; Douglas, 2009; Sprenger, 2017b).

The paper is also notable for what it does not say: that objectivity corresponds to value freedom, and that the impact of data on theory can be assessed without reference to values. A long research tradition in philosophy of science has found this ideal unattainable, especially in the context of inductive reasoning (e.g., Rudner, 1953; Hempel, 1965; Douglas, 2000; Reiss and Sprenger, 2014). With regard to the role of values in inference, I invite the authors to expand on the virtue of impartiality (Table 1, V3). Does it involve priority of evidence over values, or balancing values against each other, as Douglas (2004, 2009) suggests?

The rest of this note is devoted to removing a common misunderstanding about Bayesian inference. Gelman and Hennig write that Bayesian inference should not be limited to the analysis of subjective beliefs (p. 26). I agree, but I would like to be more radical and deny that Bayesian inference should be understood like this in the first place. Probably no Bayesian statistician thinks that the prior distribution over different parameter values mirrors her actual degrees of belief (see also Gelman and Shalizi, 2013). Rather, the prior formalizes the degrees of belief she would have on the supposition that the overarching statistical model is true. Of course, all these models are highly idealized and most probably false. The prior and posterior distribution

Contact information: Tilburg Center for Logic, Ethics and Philosophy of Science (TiLPS), Tilburg

University, P.O. Box 90153, 5000 LE Tilburg, The Netherlands. Email: j.sprenger@uvt.nl. Webpage: www.laeuferpaar.de

(3)

should not be understood as determining betting odds on the truth of the various hypotheses; rather, they express relative plausibility judgments conditional on a given model (Sprenger, 2017a).

Like anywhere in science, these judgments are only as reliable as the model from which they are derived: garbage in, garbage out. The “Falsificationist Bayesianism” discussed in Section 5.5 flows naturally from taking the subjective Bayesian approach seriously. It makes explicit that inferences within a model need to be complemented by checking the adequacy of the model itself. And I agree with Gelman and Hennig that this critical perspective is vital for Bayesians in pursuit of scientific objectivity.

References

Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive Risk and Values in Science. Philosophy of Science, 67:559– 579.

Douglas, H. (2004). The irreducible complexity of objectivity. Synthese, 138(3):453–473. Douglas, H. (2009). Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh University Press,

Pittsburgh.

Gelman, A. and Shalizi, C. R. (2013). Philosophy and the practice of Bayesian statistics. British Journal of Mathematical and Statistical Psychology, 66:8–38.

Harding, S. (1991). Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? Thinking from Women’s Lives. Cornell University Press, Ithaca.

Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of Scientific Explanation. The Free Press, New York. Longino, H. (1990). Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific

In-quiry. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

Reiss, J. and Sprenger, J. (2014). Scientific Objectivity. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Rudner, R. (1953). The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philosophy of Science, 30:1–6.

Sprenger, J. (2017a). Conditional Degree of Belief. Manuscript under review.

Sprenger, J. (2017b). The Objectivity of Subjective Bayesianism. Manuscript under review.

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

This contribution focusses on features of contemporary professional debates and reactions to social policy and reforms in five European countries (Italy, Spain,

Architecture of the Ti(IV) Sites in TiAlPO-5 Determined Using Ti K-Edge X-ray Absorption and X-ray Emission Spectroscopies / Erik Gallo;Andrea Piovano;Carlo Marini;Olivier

If the coupling between these resonators is ‘guided’ by a suspended metallic wire, dipole symmetry is imposed on the modes, which gives rise to a dipole antenna-like field pattern with

Table 4 - Confusion matrix for liqueur thujone level prediction with HS-SPME-GC-MS data.. Table 5 - Confusion matrix for liqueur thujone level prediction with

The method is based on the measurement and stabilization of the absolute length of the cavity perimeter and of the resonators formed by the opposite cavity mirrors.. The

We have used methods for multi-modal registration with transformation ranging from parametric (afne, spline) to non-parametric (based o n curvature or elastic) and

The thesis has shown that auditory interfaces can use distance cues in another way, which is the ability to discriminate between several distances, either to distinguish several

Use of all other works requires consent of the right holder (author or publisher) if not exempted from copyright protection by the