• Non ci sono risultati.

Signaling with costly acquisition of signals

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Signaling with costly acquisition of signals"

Copied!
10
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

ContentslistsavailableatScienceDirect

Journal

of

Economic

Behavior

&

Organization

jo u r n al ho me p ag e :ww w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / j e b o

Signaling

with

costly

acquisition

of

signals

Ennio

Bilancini

a,∗

,

Leonardo

Boncinelli

b

aDipartimentodiEconomia“MarcoBiagi”,UniversitàdegliStudidiModenaeReggioEmilia,VialeBerengario51,43ovest,41121

Modena,Italy

bDipartimentodiScienzeperl’Economiael’Impresa,UniversitàdegliStudidiFirenze,ViadellePandette9,50127Firenze,Italy

a

r

t

i

c

l

e

i

n

f

o

Articlehistory: Received5July2016 Receivedinrevisedform 10September2017 Accepted30October2017 Availableonline11November2017 JELclassification:

D82 D83 Keywords: Costlycognition Costlysignalacquisition Pooling

Equilibriumrefinements Forwardinduction Trembles

a

b

s

t

r

a

c

t

Inthispaperweinvestigatetheconsequencesofintroducingacosttoobservethesignal inanotherwisestandardsignalinggame.Beyondidentifyingequilibria,whichwecontrast withthoseofastandardsignalinggame,westudytheirrobustnesstotwoimportantclasses ofrefinements:actingthroughrestrictionsonout-of-equilibriumbeliefsandthrough trem-bles.Ourresultssuggestthatmoreprominenceshouldbegiventothepoolingoutcomeon theminimumsignal.

©2017ElsevierB.V.Allrightsreserved.

1. Introduction

Signalingisapervasivephenomenonineconomicinteractions,emerginginmanysituationswherethereare

informa-tionasymmetries.Manysignalingmodelshavebeendevelopedandstudied,makingtheclassofsignalinggamesaquite

prominentoneineconomics(seeRiley,2001,foracomprehensivesurvey).Animportantcharacteristicofsignalinggames

isthattheytypicallyshowmanyequilibriawithratherdistinctfeatures:equilibriainwhichsender’stypespooltogetherby

sendingthesamesignalandequilibriawheresender’stypesseparatefromeachotherbysendingdifferentsignals.

Inappliedresearch,signalingmodelsareoftenusedwiththefocusonthebestseparatingequilibrium,alsocalledthe

Rileyequilibrium,i.e.,theequilibriumwhereallsender’stypesseparatebuttheyincurtheminimumnecessarysignaling

costtodoso.ThisisingoodpartduetoanimportantstreamofliteraturethathasshowntheprominenceoftheRiley

equilibriumwhenplayersaresupposedtopossessasufficientdegreeofforwardinduction:typically,plausiblerestrictions

onout-of-equilibriumbeliefsareappliedtorefineawaymanyequilibria(seeSobel,2009,foraninstructivesurvey).

Despitetherelevanceofsignalingmodels,theliteraturehassofargivenrelativelyscarceattentiontothepossibility

thattheacquisitionofthesignalbythereceivermightbeadeliberateandcostlyactivity.Istheassumptionofautomatic

acquisitionofsignalsinnocuous?Inthispaperweshowthatitisdefinitelynotso.Indeed,evenaverysmallcostofsignal

∗ Correspondingauthor.

E-mailaddresses:ennio.bilancini@unimore.it(E.Bilancini),leonardo.boncinelli@unifi.it(L.Boncinelli). https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2017.10.022

(2)

acquisitioncanmakeagreatdifferenceintermsoftherobustness(andplausibility)ofequilibria.Inparticular,weshowthat

inthepresenceofcoststoacquirethesignalthepoolingofsender’stypescanonlyhappenontheminimum(leastcostly)

signal,whileallotherpoolingoutcomescannotbesustainedasequilibria.Atthesametime,thepoolingequilibriumonthe

minimumsignalisnotrefinedawaybyanyrestrictiononbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignals,sothatitbecomesatleastas

prominentastheRileyequilibriumasoutcomeofasignalinggame.Theseresultsaredrivenbytheemergenceofastrategic

complementarity:ifthereceiverchoosesnottoincurtheacquisitioncost,thenallsender’stypesfinditoptimaltopoolon

theminimumsignaland,atthesametime,ifthedifferenttypesofthesenderpoolonthesamesignal,thenthereceiverfinds

itoptimalnottoincurtheacquisitioncost.So,acomplementaritynaturallyarisesbetweenthereceiver’sincentivetocostly

acquirethesignalandthesender’sincentivetoengageinthecostlysignalingactivity.Thisalsoimpliesthattwodeviations

arerequired,startingfromapoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignal,foranon-equilibriumsignaltobeobservedbythe

receiver:adeviationbythesenderonlywouldnotevenbeennoticedbythereceiver.Thisintuitivelyexplainstherobustness

torestrictionsonout-of-equilibriumbeliefs.

Sinceourmodelisnotapuresignalinggame,asitalsodealswithinformationacquisitionbythereceiver,westudythe

robustnessofequilibriawhenout-of-equilibriumplayisnotduetointentionaldeviations,buttomistakesthatplayersmake

whenchoosingequilibriumstrategies.Ourmainfindingisthatthepoolingoutcomeontheminimumsignalisrobustto

tremblesonplayers’strategies,sincethebenefitsofchangingstrategyarenegligiblewhentremblesareverysmall,while

bothsignalingandsignalacquisitionimplynon-negligiblecostsforplayers.

Ourresultssuggestthatnewattentionshouldbegiventopoolingoutcomes,inparticulartopoolingontheminimum

signal.Thiscouldhavefar-reachingimplications,especiallyinthelightofthewidespreadrelianceonseparatingequilibria

inappliedmodels.

Inthispaperwealsoconsiderseparationoutcomes.Inparticular,weshowthatthesetofseparatingequilibriaisthe

samewhensignalacquisitionisautomaticandwhen,instead,isdeliberateandcostly,providedthattheacquisitioncost

issufficientlysmallrelativelytothevalueofinformation.Thesameresultholdswhenwerestrictattentiontoseparating

equilibriarefinedthroughrestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignalsandtremblesonplayers’strategies.

Thepaperisorganizedasfollows.InSection2wereviewtheliteratureoncostlyacquisitionofinformation.InSection

3weintroducesignalinggameswithcostlyacquisitionofsignalsbymeansofanexamplethatisavariantoftheclassical

Spence’ssignalingmodel.InSection4wedefineageneralclassofsignalinggameswithcostlyacquisitionofsignals.In

Section5wegiveourresultsontheequilibriaofthesegames,andhowtheyarerefinedbymeansofrestrictionsonbeliefsat

out-of-equilibriumsignalsandbymeansoftrembles.InSection6weexploretherobustnessofourresultsalonganumber

ofdimensions.Section7summarizesourcontributionandprovidesfinalremarksonwelfare.AformaldefinitionofPerfect

Bayes-NashequilibriumcanbefoundinAppendixA.ProofsarecollectedinAppendixB.

2. Relatedliterature

Theideathattheacquisitionofinformationisastrategicchoicewhichcomesatacostisreceivingincreasingattention

ineconomics.SincetheseminalcontributionbyGrossmanandStiglitz(1980),whereitisshownhowcostlyinformation

canimpairtheefficientfunctioningofmarkets,severalmodelswiththisfeaturehavebeeninvestigated,butjustafewof

themarecloselyrelatedtoourmodel.Infact,mostofthesemodelsdonotconsiderasender-receiversetup,andthosewho

considerasignalingframeworkdonotexplorethepossibilitythatinformationacquisitioninvolvesthesignalitself.1,2

Tothebestofourknowledge,theonlypapersconsideringcostlyacquisitionofinformationinsignalinggamesareBilancini

andBoncinelli(2016b),whostudythecasewherethereceiverisananalogicalreasoner,andBilanciniandBoncinelli(2016a),

whoconsiderthecaseofareceiverthathastoincuracognitivecosttofullyandpreciselyelaborateinformationonsender’s

type.AnimportantdifferencebetweenthemodelsinBilanciniandBoncinelli(2016a,b)andtheonedevelopedinthepresent

paperisthatintheformerstheacquisitioncostispaidtoacquirehardinformationonthestateoftheworld,whileinthe

presentpaperthecostispaidtoacquirethesoftinformationembodiedbythesignal.

ApapermorecloselyrelatedtooursisDewatripontandTirole(2005)whichdevelopsatheoryofcostlycommunication

whereboththesenderandthereceiverhavetoincuracostinordertocommunicate.3Themodelcanbeseenasastandard

cheaptalkmodel,withtheadditionalfeaturethatinorderforcommunicationtooccurboththesenderandthereceiver

havetoincuracost.4Duetothis,aformofstrategiccomplementarityarisesthatissimilartotheoneemerginginour

model–whichgivesrisetoarobustbabblingequilibriumwherethemessagesentbythesendercontainsnoinformationand

1 SeeforinstancetheliteratureonstrategicpricingandinformationacquisitionofproductqualityfromathirdpartystartedwithBesterandRitzberger

(2001)(seealsoGertz,2014andMartin,2015).

2 Costlyacquisitionofinformationhasbeenrecentlystudiedinanumberofdifferentsettings:costlycognition(Gabaixetal.,2006;CaplinandDean,

2014);strategicinteractiontoinfluencethirdparties(Liu,2011;Brocasetal.,2012)orthesubsequentoutcome(MorathandMünster,2013;Colomboetal., 2014);auctions(Shi,2012);voting(Oliveros,2013);expertsandauditstructure(Argenzianoetal.,2014;MenichiniandSimmons,2014).

3 Weobservethat,whilecostsarepaidbyboththesenderandthereceiver,communicationremainsone-sided.Forarecentcontributionwhere

communicationistwo-sidedandcostless,seeEs ˝oandWallace(2014).

4 TheinformativenessofcommunicationinacheaptalksettinghasbeenrecentlystudiedbyChenandGordon(2015),whogeneralizethecomparative

staticsanalysisintheseminalpaperofCrawfordandSobel(1982),andbyShimizuandIshida(2015),whoshowthattheextentofcommunicationis severelylimitedasthereceiverbecomesmoreinformed.

(3)

thereceiverdoesnotacquireit.ThemaindifferenceconcerningthesettingisthatDewatripontandTirole(2005)consider

signalsthathaveallthesamecost,whileinourmodelhighersignalsaremorecostly.Besidesconsideringadifferentsetting,

wealsocarryoutadifferentanalysisthatfocusesontherobustnessofequilibriatorefinementsactingthroughrestrictions

onbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignalsandthroughrefinementsthatarebasedonplayers’trembles.Intuitively,ourresults

abouttherobustnessofpoolingequilibriaontheminimumsignalextendinthesettingofDewatripontandTirole(2005)to

babblingequilibria.However,thefactthatdifferentsignalsentaildifferentcostsforthesenderiscrucialfortheelimination

ofpoolingequilibriathatarenotontheminimumsignal.

Inanapparentlyverydifferentsetting,SolanandYariv(2004)obtainresultsthatpartlyoverlapwithours.Theyconsider

gameswithespionage:startingfromasettingwhereeachoftwoplayershastomakeadecisionwithoutknowingthechoice

madebytheopponent,theyendowoneoftheplayerswiththepossibilitytoobservetheopponent’sactionatacostpriorto

takinghisowndecision.Amongotherthings,theyshowthatanequilibriumoftheoriginalgamewheretheopponentplaysa

purestrategywillbemaintainedincasethepossibilityofespionageisgiventotheotherplayer,whohoweverpreferstosave

espionagecostssinceinequilibriumthereisnoinformationtobeacquired.Suchresultisbasicallythesameasobservingin

oursettingthatthepoolingprofileontheminimumsignalisequilibriumforanyleveloftheacquisitioncost.5Differently

fromSolanandYariv(2004),wefocusonaspecificclassofgames,i.e.,signalinggames.Thisleadsustocomparethecase

ofpositiveacquisitioncostswiththecasewithzeroacquisitioncosts,whichcanbeseenasthestandardsignalinggame;

onthecontrary,SolanandYariv(2004)’sbasisforcomparisonisthecaseofinfinitecosts,whennoespionageoccurs.This

allowsustoshowthatpoolingprofileswhicharenotontheminimumsignalceasetobeequilibriawhenweintroducecostly

acquisitionofsignals.Furthermore,ouranalysisexplorestherobustnessofthepoolingprofileontheminimumsignalto

refinementsactingthroughrestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignals,andtorefinementsactingthroughplayers’

tremblesaswell,whereasSolanandYariv(2004)onlyconsiderespionageitselfasapotentialrefinementtool(forgames

whereoriginallythereisnoespionage).

3. Amotivatingexample

ConsiderthefollowingsimplevariantoftheclassicalmodelbySpence(1973).ThereisoneemployerEthatwantsto

hireaworkerW.Therearetwotypesofworkers,distinguishedbytheirproductivity∈{1,2},whichisaworker’sprivate

information;Ehasaprior0<p<1thatWishighlyproductive,i.e.,that=2.Technologyandmarketconditionsaresuch

thatE’snetprofitsaregivenby−wifaworkerishired,withwthewagepaidtothehiredworkerandhisproductivity,

whileotherwiseprofitsare0.

Moreover,Wcanacquireeducationbyincurringacostthatistype-dependent.Inparticular,supposethatWcomesfroma

foreigncountryandthathehastomovetoE’scountryinordertobehired.SupposealsothatWcanonlyacquireeducationin

theforeigncountry,andthattheonlyavailablealternativesareagoodschoolGandabadschoolB,whicharenotpreviously

knowntoE.Fortheprospectiveworkeroftype,thecostofattendingGis2/andthecostofattendingschoolBis1/.

So,attendingschoolGismorecostlythanattendingschoolB,anditisrelativelymoresoforthelowtype(i.e.,=1).This

providesWwithacostlysignalx∈{G,B}thatpotentiallyallowsW’stypestoseparate.

Sofar,thereisnosubstantialdifferencefromSpence’smodel.However,whatifE,inordertoassessthequalityofthe

schoolingsignalxsentbyW,hastoactivelyacquiretheinformationonwhatschoolWhasattendedinthecountryhecomes

from,andwhatattendancecostshavebeenpaid?Thisinformationcanwellnotcomeforfreeandourpointisthatthiscan

makethedifference.Weobservethatthecostsofacquiringsuchinformationcanbeinterpretedasduetothematerialand

thecognitiveeffortwhichisnecessarytoretrieveandelaboratetherelevantdataonx.Onthematerialside,Emighthaveto

searchandcollectinformationonGandB,andmaybealsopaytotranslatedocumentsthatwouldbeotherwiseinaccessible.

Onthecognitiveside,Emighthavetoexertefforttoelaboratethecollectedinformationinordertoestablishthatoneschool

isGwithcosts2andtheotherisBwithcostsandtoassignthesignalxtoeitherGorB.Ifno(materialorcognitive)effort

isexerted,thenschoolsarefundamentallyindistinguishabletoE;inthiscase,itisreasonablethatEdoesnotconditionher

decisiononx.Tomodelthis,supposethatEhastopayacostc>0toacquirethesignalxsentbyW.Inparticular,ifEdoes

notincurthecostc,thensignalxremainsunknowntoE.

Considernowthefollowingsituation:WchoosesBindependentlyofhistype,i.e.,x(1)=x(2)=B,andEdecidesnotto

acquirethesignalx.Itiseasytocheckthatthisisanequilibriuminthepresentexample(whateveristhevalueforEof

knowingW’stypes):bothtypesofWstrictlylosebyswitchingtothemorecostlyGasthisdoesnotgrantadifferentwage,

andEstrictlylosesbyacquiringthesignalbecauseitcostscandprovidesnonewinformation.Weobservethatsuchan

equilibriumisverysimilartothepoolingequilibriumwithlowestsignalthatemergesinSpence’smodel.However,thereis

animportantdifference:becauseofacquisitioncostssuchpoolingequilibriumismuchmorerobusttorefinementsthanthe

oneinSpence’smodel.Firstly,wenotethatrestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignalsareineffectivetorefineaway

thisequilibrium,sinceEdoesnotacquireanysignal,andhenceWcannotuseout-of-equilibriumsignalstocommunicate

withE;indeed,a deviationbyWonlywouldnotevenbeennoticedbyE.Inparticular,evenifW’shightypedeviates

fromx(2)=Btox(2)=G,whenEdecidesnottoacquirethesignalthereisnowaytoletEknow–orevenimagine–about

suchadeviation.So,argumentsbasedonthereasonablenessofout-of-equilibriumbeliefscannotrefineawaythispooling

(4)

equilibrium.Secondly,thispoolingequilibriumisrobustevenwhendeviationsfromequilibriumbehaviorisnotintentional

buttheresultofmistakes.Indeed,whentheprobabilityofmistakesbecomessufficientlylow,thepossiblebenefitofchanging

strategyisnotworthitscostforbothplayers,sincechoosingGismorecostlythanchoosingBforW,andacquiringthesignal

iscostlyforEaswell.

Thereisanotherimportantdifference.Inthisexamplethepoolingoutcomeassociatedwiththelowestsignalpooling

equilibriumistheonlypoolingoutcomethatcanbesustainedinequilibrium,whichisincontrastwithSpence’smodel

wheremultiplepoolingoutcomesarepossibleinequilibrium.Thishappenswithoutanyadditionalrefinementofequilibria.

Toseewhyitisso,considerthecasewherebothtypesofWpoolonG,i.e.,x(1)=x(2)=G.GiventhisbehaviorbyW,Efinds

itstrictlyprofitablenottoincurtheacquisitioncost,asacquiringthesignalprovidesnonewinformation.ButifEdoesnot

acquirethesignalx,thenthechoiceofx(1)=x(2)=GcannotbesustainedinequilibriumsinceeachofW’stypewouldstrictly

gainbyswitchingfromGtoB,asthisallowstosaveonthecostofsignalingwithoutadverselyaffectingE’sbeliefs.

4. Themodel

Wenowintroducethemoregeneralgameofsignalingwithcostlyacquisitionofsignals(SCAS).ThereisonesenderSand

onereceiverR(sometimesreferredtoas“he”and“she”,respectively).ThesenderSobserveshisowntypet∈T,withTa

finitesetofcardinalityn,andthenchoosesasignalx ∈X=R+.6ThereceiverRcanexertcostlyeffortandacquirethesignal

x,orsaveoneffortandobservenothing.Wedenotewiths{s1,s2}suchachoice,wheres1meansthatxisnotacquired

ands2meansthatxisacquiredandeffortisexerted.7Inanycase,thenRhastochooseanactionyY=R.Thepriorbeliefs

heldbyRonTaregivenbyp=(p1,...,pn)∈T,whereptdenotestheprobabilitythatSisoftypet∈T,andTdenotesthe

unit(n−1)-simplex.TheposteriorbeliefsheldbyR,onceasignalxhasbeensentandaninformationacquisitionchoices

hasbeenmade,aredenotedbyˇ(x,s)=(ˇ1(x,s),...,ˇn(x,s))∈T,whereeachˇt(x,s)istheprobabilitythatSisoftypet

conditionalon(x,s).Consistentlywiththeideathatnosignalisobservedincases=s1,weassumethatˇ(x,s1)=ˇ(x,s1)for

allx,x∈X.

UtilityforSisU:T×X×Y→R,andutilityforRisV:T×X×Y×{s1,s2}→R.WeassumethatUisstrictlyincreasingin

y,andstrictlydecreasinginx.WealsoassumethatVexhibitsafixedpositivecostofacquiringthesignal,sothatthenotation

canbesimplifiedasfollows:V(t,x,y,s1)=

v

(t,x,y)andV(t,x,y,s2)=

v

(t,x,y)−c,forallt∈T,x∈X,y∈Y.Moreover,we

assumethatargmax

y∈Y



t∈Tˇt

v

(t,x,y)isasingleton,forallˇ∈T,andallx∈X.Finally,thesingle-crossingpropertyis

assumedtohold:U(t,x,y)≤U(t,x,y),withx>x,impliesthatU(t,x,y)<U(t,x,y)forallt>tandy,y∈Y.

Welimitouranalysistopurestrategies.AstrategyforSisafunction:T→X;wedenotewithMthesetofallpossible

.AstrategyforRisapair(s,˛)wheres∈{s1,s2}and˛:X×{s1,s2}→Yisafunctionsuchthat˛(x,s1)=˛(x,s1)forallx,

x∈X,i.e.,R’sactionisunconditionalonxwhenevers=s1ischosen;wedenotewithAthesetofallsuchfunctions.8

Lastly,inordertobettercontrastourresultswiththeresultsonstandardsignalinggameswefinditusefultodefinea

classofgamesthatareequivalenttostandardsignalinggamesandthatcanbeobtainedfromaSCASgame.Thiscanbedone,

startingfromaSCASgame,byforcingRtoplays=s2.Werefertosuchgameassignalingwithforcedacquisitionofsignals

(SFAS).NotethataSFASgamewithutilitiesUand

v

isactuallythestandardsignalinggame–i.e.,withnocoststoacquire

thesignal–thatcanbeobtainedfromaSCASgamewithutilitiesUand

v

andanyacquisitioncostc>0.

5. Results

5.1. Equilibria

AsasolutionconceptwefocusonPerfectBayes-Nashequilibria(seeAppendixAforaformaldefinitionappliedtoSCAS

gamesandSFASgames).Apoolingequilibriumisaprofile(,(s,˛))suchthat(t)=(t)forallt,tT.Apoolingequilibrium

ontheminimumsignalisaprofile(,(s,˛))suchthat(t)=0forallt∈T.A(fullyorpartially)separatingequilibriumisa

profile(,(s,˛))suchthat(t) /=(t)forsomet,tT.

InaSFASgame,givenasender’sstrategy,wedefinethevalueofacquiringinformationonthesignalas:

()=max ˛∈A



t∈T pt

v

(t,(t),˛((t),s2))−max ˛∈A



t∈T pt

v

(t,(t),˛((t),s1)). (1)

6 Wehavechosentousecontinuousactionspacesbecausethisisthemostcommonsettingforsignalingmodels.Westressthatourresultsmightbe

stated,withfewstraightforwardadjustments,usingdiscreteactionspacestoo.

7 Thislabelingowestotheclassificationofelaborationprocessesas“System1”,orS1,whichisfast,cheapandintuitive,and“System2”,orS2,which

isslow,costlyandanalytical(see,e.g.,Kahneman,2003).Westressthisinterpretationbasedoncognitiveeffortbecausewethinkthatitappliestomany relevantcasesofsignalacquisition.Ofcourse,otherinterpretationsarepossiblewherethecostofacquiringthesignalisduetonon-cognitivefactors.

8 HereweadoptaspecificationofstrategiesforRthatismorecompactbutperhapslessstraightforwardthan,e.g.,˛(s,˛s1,˛s2)where˛s1∈Yisthe

actionchosenifs=s1and˛s2:XYistheactionchosenifs=s2.Westressthatthetwoformulationsareequivalentinthesensethatwecangofromone

totheotherbycoalescing(Thompson,1952)theinformationsetthatRreacheswhens=s1withtheonewhereRchoosess,althoughinthisgamethereis

(5)

ThesetofPerfectBayes-NashequilibriaofaSCASgameisingeneraldifferentfromthesetofPerfectBayes-Nashequilibria

ofatypicalsignalinggame(aSFASgameinoursetting).Proposition1belowstatesthatpoolingequilibriaontheminimum

signalhaveaparticularroleinSCASgamesbecause,whiletheyalsoexistinordinarySFASgames,theyaretheonlypooling

equilibriainSCASgames.Also,Proposition1statesthatthesetofseparatingequilibriaoftheSCASgameisincludedinthe

setofseparatingequilibriaoftheSFASgame:indeed,aseparatingequilibriumoftheSCASgameisaseparatingequilibrium

oftheSFASgamewiththeadditionalrequirementthatthecosttoacquirethesignalisnotlargerthanthevalueofacquiring

informationonthesignal.

Proposition1. ConsideraSCASgameanditsassociatedSFASgame.

(a)ApoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignalexistsbothintheSCASgameandintheSFASgame;moreover,intheSCASgame

nopoolingequilibriumexistswhichisnotontheminimumsignal.

(b) If(,(s,˛))isaseparatingequilibriumintheSCASgame,thenitisalsoaseparatingequilibriumintheSFASgame;if(,(s2,

˛))isaseparatingequilibriumintheSFASgame,thenitisaseparatingequilibriumintheSCASgameifandonlyifc≤().

Weobservethatitfollowsfromstandardresultsonsignalinggameswithoutacquisitioncoststhatpoolingequilibriacan

existintheSFASgamewherethesignalchosenbyallS’stypesisnottheminimum.Therefore,inasensethesetofseparating

equilibriaofaSCASgameconvergestothatoftheassociatedSFASgameasctendsto0,whereasthesameisnottrueof

thesetofpoolingequilibria.Wealsoobservethatascgetslargerandlarger,thesetofequilibriaofaSCASgameshrinks.

Indeed,aseparatingprofile(,(s2,˛))whichisequilibriumofaSCASgameceasestosuchwhencexceedsitsvalue()

ofacquiringinformationonthesignal.Further,sincethevalueofacquiringinformationonthesignalonlydependsonits

informativenessaboutsender’stypes,allseparatingequilibriawiththesamevalueceasetoexistatthesametime.Tofix

ideas,considerasignalingmodelwithonlytwotypesofsenders:theentiresetofseparatingequilibriaoftheSFASgameis

maintainedintheSCASgamewhencdoesnotexceedthevalueforthereceivertoacquiretheinformationonthesender’s

currenttype,whichisthesameforallseparatingstrategiesofthesender;however,whencexceedssuchvalue,allseparating

equilibriaceasetoexistinthisSCASgame.Finally,fromProposition1wecanalsoconcludethatseparatingequilibriawhere

aremoreinformativewilldisappearathighercostlevelsthanthosewhicharelessinformative(think,forinstance,ofafully

separatingequilibriumcomparedtoapartiallyseparatingequilibrium).Moreprecisely,asignalingstrategyfortheSender

canbeseenasaninformation-revealingexperiment,andaccordingtotheBlackwell’stheorem(Blackwelletal.,1951,1953),

themoreinformativeanexperimentthehigheritsvalueforanyexpected-utilitymaximizingdecision-maker.

5.2. Refinements

Giventhemultiplicityofequilibriain asignalinggames(aSCASgame isnotanexceptiontothis),somenotionof

equilibriumrefinementisoftenappliedtogetridofimplausibleequilibria.So,evenifthesetofequilibriaofaSCASgame

differsfromthatofaSFASgame,anequivalencemightberestoredthroughrefinements.Inthefollowingwearguethatthis

isnotthecase.

Animportantclassofrefinementsappliedtosignalinggamesfollowtheideathatout-of-equilibriumbeliefsshouldnot

betotallyfree,butneedtosatisfysomecriterionofreasonableness.9Withtheaimofextendingsuchclassofrefinements

toSCASgames,wedefinethenotionofrobustnesstorestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignals,andinpoint

(a)ofProposition2weshowthatinaSCASgametheequilibriumwhereallsender’stypespoolontheminimumsignal

satisfiessuchrobustnesscriterion.Indeed,refinementsactingthroughrestrictionsonout-of-equilibriumbeliefsrelyonthe

possibilitythatadeviationbythesendertriggersapathofplayalongwhichthereceivergetssomepieceofinformationthatis

unexpectedalongtheequilibriumpath;butinapoolingequilibriumofaSCASgamethereceiverdoesnotacquirethesignal,

sothatthispossibilitydoesnotexist.Thisiswhyrefinementsactingthroughrestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibrium

signalsdonothaveabiteinsuchcase.Wenowformalize,forSCASandSFASgames,theconceptofanequilibriumprofile

thatisrobusttorestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignals.Givenasender’sstrategy,wedenotewithXe()the

setofsignalsthatarechosenbyatleastonesender’stype,i.e.,Xe()={xX:

tT,(t)=x}.Similarly,wedenotewith

Xo()thesetofsignalsthatarenotchosenbyanysender’stype,i.e.,Xo()=X\Xe.Moreover,givenasender’sstrategy,

arestrictiononbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignalsisacollectionofsets{B(x,s2)}x∈Xo(),withB(x,s)⊆T,B(x,s)/=∅.10An

equilibriumissaidtoberobusttoarestrictiononbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignalsifitiscompatiblewiththerestricted

setofadmissiblebeliefs.11

Wearereadyforthefollowingpropositionontherobustnessofequilibriatorestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibrium

signals.

9Anon-exhaustivelistofrefinementsactingthroughrestrictionsonout-of-equilibriumbeliefsinclude:theIntuitiveCriterion(ChoandKreps,1987),

Divinity(BanksandSobel,1987),D1(ChoandKreps,1987),D2(ChoandKreps,1987),theUndefeatedEquilibrium(Mailathetal.,1993).

10WeobservethatevenasignalxXe()triggersanout-of-equilibriumbeliefifthereceiverdeviatesfroms1tos2.However,suchbeliefsarealready

restrictedbythedefinitionofPerfectBayesNashequilibriumgiveninAppendixA(seetheE3.2requirement).

11Moreformally,itmustsatisfythedefinitionofaperfectBayes-NashequilibriumwithastrengtheningoftheE3.3requirement(seeAppendixA),that

(6)

Proposition2. ConsideraSCASgameanditsassociatedSFASgame.

(a)IntheSCASgame,givensuchthat(t)=0forallt∈T,foranyrestrictiononbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignalsthereexists

(s,˛)suchthat(,(s,˛))isapoolingequilibriumrobusttotherestriction.

(b)If(,(s,˛))isaseparatingequilibriumthatisrobusttoagivenrestrictiononbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignalsinthe

SCASgame,thenitisalsoaseparatingequilibriumthatisrobusttothesamerestrictionintheSFASgame;if(,(s2,˛))isa

separatingequilibriumoftheSFASgamethatisrobusttoagivenrestrictiononbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignals,thenitis

aseparatingequilibriumoftheSCASgamethatisrobusttothesamerestrictionifandonlyifc≤().

Weremarkthat,inpoint(b)ofProposition2,refinementsactingthroughrestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibrium

signals,evenifineffectiveagainstpoolingequilibriaontheminimumsignal,allowtogetridofmanyseparatingequilibriaof

theSCASgame,inamannersimilartowhattheydoinasignalinggamewithoutcostlyacquisitionofsignals.Indeed,inany

separatingequilibriumRmustbeplayings2,sothatadeviationbySallowstoreachanout-of-equilibriuminformationset

ofR,wherethefreedominthechoiceofbeliefsisnowrestrictedbytherefinementunderconsideration,possiblyinducing

RtoplayinawaythatisfavorabletoS.

Thereisanotherclassofrefinementswhichconsidersout-of-equilibriumplaynotasintentionaldeviations,butasthe

resultofmistakesthatplayersmakewhenchoosingequilibriumstrategies.12Theserefinementsrequireplayers’strategies

tobeoptimalagainstcompletelymixedstrategyprofilesthatapproachtheequilibriumprofile.Proposition3establishes,

inpoint(a),therobustnessofthepoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignalwithrespecttoanykindoftrembles.The

intuitionisasfollows.Startingfromthepoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignal,ifRisforcedtochooses2withsome

smallprobabilityduetotrembles,thenSmayhavesomeincentivetooptforasignalthatisnottheminimum;however,

sincesignalingisacostlyactivity,ifthetrembleissufficientlysmallthenthebenefitfromsignalingfallsshortofthecost.

AnanalogousreasoningappliesifweconsiderR’soptimalbehaviorwhenS’schoiceistrembling,duetothefactthats2is

morecostlythans1.

Toformalizetheideaofrobustnesstoanykindoftrembles,wemakeuseofthenotionoftrulyperfectequilibrium

(Kohlberg,1981).13Topresentitformally,wehavefirsttomodifyoursettingbyconsideringafinitesetofsignals ˆX,with

0∈ ˆX,andafinitesetofactions ˆY,sothatthesetofstrategiesisalsofiniteforbothSandR,whichwedenotewith ˆM and

{s1,s2}× ˆA.14Moreover,wehavetointroducemixedstrategiestomodelplayers’tremblesinthechoiceofstrategies.We

denotebySamixedstrategyforS,withS()indicatingtheprobabilityattachedtopurestrategy.Similarly,wedenote

byRamixedstrategyforR,withR(s,˛)indicatingtheprobabilityattachedtopurestrategy(s,˛).WenotethatinaSFAS

gameR(s1,˛)=0forall˛∈ ˆA,sinces1cannotbechosenbyReitherbymistake.Givenaprofile(S,R),werefertoa

trembleasasequenceofcompletelymixedstrategyprofiles(Sk,k

R)k=1,...,∞suchthat(Sk,Rk)→(S,R)ask→∞.Given

adegeneratemixedstrategyprofile(S,R)whereS()=1andR(s,˛)=1,andatremble(Sk,Rk)k=1,...,∞,wesaythat

(,(s,˛))isrobusttothetrembleifthereexists ˆk suchthat,forallk≥ ˆk,isbestreplyagainstk

R and(s,˛)isbestreply

againstk

S;furthermore,wesaythat(,(s,˛))isatrulyperfectequilibriumif(,(s,˛))isrobusttoeverytremble.Finally,to

simplifythestatementofProposition3,weintroducethefollowingdefinition:givenadegeneratemixedstrategyprofile,a

trembleintheSCASgame(Sk,k

R)k=1,...,∞,andatrembleintheSFASgame(ˆSk,ˆRk)k=1,...,∞,wesaythatthesetwotrembles

areequivalentif(i)forevery∈ ˆM,theexpectedutilityforSofplayingisthesameagainstk

RandˆRk,forallk,and(ii)

forevery(s,˛)∈{s1,s2}× ˆA,theexpectedutilityforRofplaying(s,˛)isthesameagainstk

SandˆSk,forallk.

Wearereadyforthefollowingpropositionontherobustnessofequilibriatoplayers’trembles.

Proposition3. ConsideraSCASgamewithfinitesetsofsignalsandactions,anditsassociatedSFASgame.

(a)IntheSCASgame,anypoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignalisatrulyperfectequilibrium.

(b)If(,(s,˛))isaseparatingequilibriumthatisrobusttoagiventrembleintheSCASgame,thenitisalsoaseparatingequilibrium

thatisrobusttoanequivalenttrembleintheSFASgame;if(,(s2,˛))isaseparatingequilibriumthatisrobusttoagiven

trembleintheSFASgame,thenitisaseparatingequilibriumthatisrobusttoanequivalenttrembleintheSCASgameifc<().

Weremarkthat,inpoint(b)ofProposition3,similarlytowhathappensforrestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibrium

signals,thesetofseparatingequilibriathatarerobusttoagiventrembleisthesameinaSCASgameandintheassociated

SFASgame,providedthatacquisitioncostsaresmallenough.15Onthewhole,wecanreinforceanobservationalreadymade

afterProposition1:itisnotonlythesetofseparatingequilibriaofaSCASgame,butthesetoftheseparatingequilibria

12 Anotherpossibilityistoconsiderperturbationsinpayoffs,ratherthaninthechoiceofstrategies.Arefinementbasedonthisideaistheessential

equilibrium(Wen-TsunandJia-He,1962).

13 Indeed,atrulyperfectequilibriumisperfect(Selten,1975),proper(Myerson,1978),strictlyperfect(Okada,1981),strictlyproper(VanDamme,1991).

Moreover,atrulyperfectequilibriumcanbeseenasaone-pointsetthatisKohlberg-Mertensstable(KohlbergandMertens,1986).

14 TheresultsinProposition1holdinthissettingwithfinitestrategysetsaswell.

(7)

thatarerobusttorefinements(belief-basedortremble-based),whichconvergestotheanalogoussetoftheassociatedSFAS

gameasctendsto0.

Onefurtherremarkthatmaybeworthdoingconcernstheinabilityoftremble-basedrefinementstorestrictR’sbehavior

atinformationsetswhereanon-minimumsignalhasbeenchosen,andRhasalreadychosens2.Weobservethatsuch

informationsetscannotbereachedbymeansofS’smistakesonly;indeed,amistakebyRwhenchoosingbetweens1and

s2isalsorequired.Inordertorecoversomerefiningpowerfortremblesattheabove-mentionedinformationsets,wemay

resorttotheagent-normalformgameandapplytremblesattheagentlevel,withtheresultthatoptimalbehaviorwould

berequiredatsuchinformationsetsaswell.InthiscaseastatementsimilartotheoneinProposition2applies:forany

sequenceoftremblesthereexistsapoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignalthatiscomprisedofstrategiesthatarebest

repliesagainsteachsufficiently-large-indexedelementofthesequence.

Onelastremarkisabouttheroleoftheassumptionthatsignalacquisitionisadeliberateandcostlychoicefortheresults

inPropositions2and3.Havingachoiceforthereceiverbetweens1ands2iswhatreallymatterstoobtainthatthepooling

outcomeontheminimumsignalisrobusttorestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignals;indeed,ifRchoosess1

thenheswitchesoffherlisteningability,andhenceanysender’sdeviationisnotobservable.Therobustnesstorefinements

basedonplayers’trembles,instead,dependsnotonlyonRchoosingtolisten(s2)ornottolisten(s1),butalsoonthefact

thats2ismorecostlythans1,whichmakess1strictlybetterthans2whenSischoosingapoolingstrategyandtremblesare

smallenough.

6. Discussion

Inthissectionwediscusstherobustnessofourresultsifweassumeasmoothprocessofinformationacquisitionbythe

receiver(Section6.1),ifthesenderhasthepossibilitytoinvitethereceivertoacquirethesignal(Section6.2),ifthesignalis

notpurelycostlytothesender(Section6.3),andifthereceivercancommittoacquirethesignal(Section6.4).Thediscussion

iskeptataninformallevel.

6.1. Smoothacquisitioncosts

InthispaperwehaveconsideredamodelthatisreminiscentofReis(2006):acquisitionofinformationisalways

all-or-nothing,andsignalacquisitionisbinary,i.e.,Reitherpaystheacquisitioncostandacquiresxwithcertainty,orpaysnothing

andacquiresnothing.Onecaninsteadthinkoftheprocessofsignalacquisitionasasmoothoruncertainone:thegreater

thecostincurredtoacquirethesignal,thegreatertheacquisitionofthesignalcontentorthelikelihoodthatacquisitionis

successful.Inthisrespect,anaturalquestiontoaskiswhetherseparationofsender’stypesbecomesmorelikelyundersuch

asmoothoruncertainprocess.Ingeneral,theliteraturehasshownthattheinformationacquisitiontechnologydoesmatter

fortheselectionofequilibria(seeYang,2015andDenti,2016forrecentcontributionsontheissue).Whatwearguehereis

thatthepoolingoutcomeretainsitsprominencealsowhensignalacquisitionisnotall-or-nothingorisnotbinary.

Asimplewaytomodelasmoothprocessofsignalacquisitionthatisnotbinaryistoconsiderastochasticacquisition

wheretheprobabilityofacquiringxisanincreasingfunctionofthecostpaid.SupposeRhasthepossibilitytochoosealevel

ofacquisitionefforte∈[0,1],whichreplacesthechoiceofs∈{s1,s2};also,withprobability1−enosignalisacquired,

whilewithprobabilityethesignalisacquired.

Asimplewaytomodelasmoothprocessofsignalacquisitionthatisnotall-or-nothingistohavethesignalxalways

acquiredbutwithsomeblurringnoisewhoseimpactnegativelydependsontheacquisitioneffort,sothatthesignalobserved

isequaltothesignalsentplusanoisyterm.Wedenotewith∈[0,+∞)theprecision(i.e.,theinverseofthevariance)of

thenoisyterm,whichischosenbythereceiver.

Weobservethatthepoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignalisstillsupportedbyaformofstrategiccomplementarity

inbothmodelssketchedabove:ifSchoosesx=0forallt∈T,thenRhasnoreasontospendinsignalacquisition,therefore

R’soptimalchoiceise=0(thesignalisneveracquired)or=0(thesignaliscompletelyuninformative);ifRchoosese=0,

or=0,thenShasnoreasontospendincostlysignaling,thereforeS’soptimalchoiceisx=0forallt∈T.Moreover,note

thatwhene=0noout-of-equilibriuminformationsetofRcanbereachedbymeansofasingledeviationbyS,andwhen

=0noout-of-equilibriuminformationsetexists,inthatzeroprecisionofthesignaldoesnotconstrainthesetofpossible

signals.InbothcasesintentionaldeviationsbySareineffectiveattriggeringadifferentpathofplaybyR;thisintuitively

leadstotherobustnessofthepoolingoutcomeontheminimumsignaltorefinementsactingthroughrestrictionson

out-of-equilibriumbeliefs.Finally,notethatnobenefitcanbeobtainedbyunilateraldeviationstoe>0,or>0,andtox>0,while

suchdeviationswouldentailastrictlylargercost;thisallowsustoconcludethatthepoolingoutcomeontheminimum

signalisalsorobusttorefinementsbasedonplayers’trembles,inaversionofthesegameswithfinitestrategysets.

6.2. Invitingtoacquirethesignalthroughfurthersignaling

ItseemsnaturaltoaskwhethertheprominenceofseparationisrestoredifShasthepossibilitytocommunicatetoRthat

heisactuallysendinganinformativesignal–i.e.,asignalthatseparates(atleastpartly)types–andthatthereforethesignal

(8)

Onecanthinkofmanysituationswhereindeedthesendercansend,togetherwiththemainsignalx,anaccompanying

costlysignal,sayz,thatactsasaninvitationforthereceivertoengageinthecostlyacquisitionofx.Weargueherethat,in

fact,notmuchcanberestoredbytheuseofz.

Wenotethatinthissettinginformationontypescanbetransmitted,i.e.,separationcanoccur,eitheronxoronz,but

notonboth.Thisissobecause,ifseparationisattainedonx(oronz)andthereceiveracquiresx(orz),thenalltypeswould

strictlyprefertosaveoncostsandpoolonanullz(orx),andsimilarlythereceiverwouldstrictlyprefernottoincurthecost

ofacquiringz(orx),sinceitsacquisitionwouldaddnousefulinformation.So,supposethatseparationiseffectivelyattained

onzonly.Inorderforthiskindofseparationtobemorerobustthanapoolingequilibrium,itisnecessarythatthesender’s

utilityfunctionsatisfiesanequivalentofthesingle-crossingpropertyontypesandz,whichisnotguaranteedingeneral.

Evenifsuchanecessaryconditionholds,torestoretheprominenceofseparationthereceivermustacquirezautomatically.

Infact,iftheacquisitionofzrequiresadeliberatechoiceandiscostlytoR,thenthekindofstrategiccomplementarity

betweensignalingandacquiringthesignalthatwehaveillustratedfortheSCASgameisatworkhereaswell;moreover,

out-of-equilibriuminformationsetsarenotreachablethroughdeviationsbySonlywhenstartingfromthepoolingoutcome

ontheminimumsignal,andalsounilateraldeviationsfromitwouldbestrictlycostlyforbothSandR.Therefore,results

similartothosefortheSCASgamecanbeintuitivelyobtainedinthissetupaswell.

6.3. Signalnotpurelycostlytothesender

TheSCASgamestudiedinthispaperaccommodatescaseswherethesignalxispurelydissipative–itisalwaysanetcost

forSandofnointrinsicutility(orsomedisutility)forR–aswellascaseswherethesignalxisofsomeintrinsicvaluetothe

receiver.However,themodeldoesnotaccommodatethecasewherexisnotapurenetcostforthesender.

Inourmodel,allsender’stypesstrictlyprefer,otherthingsbeingequal,tosetx=0:

x∗(t,y)argmax

x∈X

U(t,x,y)=0, forall t ∈T,y∈Y. (2)

ItturnsoutthatthekindofstrategiccomplementaritythatsupportsthepoolingoutcomeinaSCASgamemaynotexistif(2)

doesnothold.However,westressthatwhatiscrucialtoourresultsisnotthat0isthecommonbestsignalforallsender’s

typesintheabsenceofasignalingvalue–anassumptionwhich,infact,caneasilybesubstitutedwithacommonoptimal

x*>0foralltT;whatreallymattersfortheexistenceoftheneededstrategiccomplementarityisthatacommonbestsignal

existsforalltypes.Toseewhy,considertheextremecasewherex*(t,y)isone-to-oneintforanygiveny.Thisimpliesthat,in

thecasethatRchoosess=s1,eachsender’stypefindsitoptimaltochooseadistinctx.Iftheinformationaboutthesender’s

typeissufficientlyvaluabletoR,itbecomesimpossibleforaprofilewithnosignalacquisitiontobeanequilibriumbecause

typesseparateindependentlyofR’sbehavior,andthereforeRalwaysfinditoptimaltoacquirethesignal.Therefore,inthe

absenceofacommonsetsignalforalltypes,thepoolingoutcomeontheminimumsignalwouldevenfailtobeaPerfect

Bayes-Nashequilibrium.

Letusconcludewithafewremarksthat,inouropinion,indicatethatacquisitioncosts–andingeneraltheanalysis

conductedinthispaper–mightberelevantevenwhen(2)doesnothold.

Oneremarkregardstherefinementpotentialofarbitrarilysmallacquisitioncostsinastandardsignalinggame.Note

thatifx*(t,y)isone-to-oneintforanygiveny,thentheincentiveforS’stypestoseparatedoesnotcomefromthefact

thatRacquiresthesignal,butfromthefactthateachtypehasitsownpreferredx.Thisrulesoutallpoolingequilibriain

aSCASgame,butitdoesnotsointheassociatedSFASgame(i.e.,inastandardsignalinggame).Infact,inaSFASgame

Ralwayschoosess=s2,andinparticularitdoessoalsowhenallS’stypespoolonthesame ¯x;thisallowsforbeliefsat

out-of-equilibriumsignalsonthepartofRthatharshlypunishtypeswhodeviatefrom ¯x,sustainingthepoolingequilibrium.

InaSCASgame,instead,Rwouldswitchfroms=s2tos=s1,leavingeachtypet∈Tfreetoswitchtohispreferredx*(t,

y).Perhapsinterestingly,thisargumentshowsthatanarbitrarilysmallacquisitioncostrulesoutallpoolingequilibriain

signalinggameswheretypesstrictlypreferdifferentsignallevels.

Anotherremarkregardsthepotentialbackfiringofmandatorydisclosurepolicies.ConsideraSCASgamewherex

repre-sentscostlydisclosureofsomecharacteristiconthepartofthesender,andsupposethatapublicauthoritywantstokeepx

aboveacertainthreshold.Ifx*(t,y)isone-to-oneintfortherelevantrangeofy,thensomedisclosurewillcertainlyhappen

asnopoolingcanbesustainedinequilibrium.However,ifthepublicauthorityimposesaminimum ¯x,thenitcanhappen

thatseparationcollapsesandapoolingequilibriumon ¯xwithnosignalacquisitionemerges.Inparticular,thiscanhappen

whenever ¯x≥maxt∈Tx∗(t, ¯y),where ¯y isthebestactionforRunders1whenalltypespoolon ¯x (forsmallervaluesof ¯x a

partialpoolingcanemerge,instead).Thismayleadtoalossintermsofinformationtransmissionthatmorethanoffsetsthe

targetedbenefitsofahighx.

6.4. Publiclycommittingtoacquirethesignal

IntheSCASgamestudiedinSections4and5,aswellasinthevariantsdiscussedinSections6.1,6.2,and6.3,there

isnopossibilityforthesender,priortochoosingthesignal,toobservethechoiceofthereceiverbetweenacquiringand

notacquiringthesignal.ThisneglectedcaseisstrategicallyequivalenttoasituationwherethereceiverRmustpublicly

(9)

complicatedtoseethatifRcanpubliclycommittoagivens∈{s1,s2},andinformationissufficientlyvaluabletoher,then

theprominenceofseparationisrestored.ConsideravariantoftheSCASgamewhereRmust16initiallycommitherselfto

choose ¯s∈{s1,s2}andsupposealsothatsuchcommitmentisobservedbySbeforehechooseswhatsignaltosend.This

configuresanadditionalinitialstageofthegamewhereRannounces ¯s,followedbyasecondstageofthegamewhereS

choosesthesignalx,andthenathirdstagewhereRplays ¯s andchoosesanactiony.Inthissetup,Scanconditionthechoice

ofthesignalon ¯s,sothathisstrategyisnowrepresentedbyfunction¯ :T×{s1,s2}→X.Notethatthissetupconfigures

twodistinctsubgames:onesignaling(sub)gameinwhichRhascommittedtos1andSknowsthathissignalwillneverbe

acquiredbyR(basically,signallingisimpossible),andanothersignaling(sub)gamewhereRhascommittedtos2andSknows

thathissignalwillalwaysbeacquired(basically,theassociatedSFASgame).Suchdynamicstructureofthegamenaturally

callsforanequilibriumconceptthatentailsbackwardreasoning.Asimplewaytodosoistolookforsubgameperfection

afterhavingrefinedtheequilibriaofeachsignalingsubgameusingstandardrefinementsactingthroughout-of-equilibrium

beliefs.

InthesignalingsubgamewhereRhascommittedtos1,thereisjustonePerfectBayes-Nashequilibrium:alltypesofS

poolonx=0,sincex>0iscostlyandSiscertainthatRwillneverobservex.DenoteS’sstrategyinthissubgamewithP,

withP(t)=0forallt.InthesignalingsubgamewhereRhascommittedtos2,therearemanyPerfectBayes-Nashequilibria,

bothpoolingandseparating.Sincethecostcofchoosings2issunk,inthissubgamethereareexactlythesameequilibriaof

theassociatedSFASgame,i.e.,theyarethesameofastandardsignalinggame.

Weconsiderherethetypicalcasewherethebestfullyseparatingequilibriumstandsupasmostprominent,i.e.,wefocus

ontheequilibriumwhereallsender’stypesseparateandeachtypespendsonsignalxtheminimumrequiredforseparation

(Riley,2001).DenoteS’sstrategyinthisequilibriumwithS.So,S’sstrategyinthefullgamecanbewrittenas¯ =(P,S).

Usingbackwardreasoning,Ranticipatesthatbycommittingtos1shewillendupinapoolingequilibriumwhereshe

playstheoptimalyagainstthebeliefsassociatedwithnosignalacquisition,whilebycommittingtos2shewillendupin

afullyseparatingequilibriumwheresheplays,foreacht,y(t)∈argmaxy∈Yu(t,S(t),y).Iftheinformationconveyedby

SisvaluabletoRintheSFASgame,thenitisstraightforwardtoseethatforapositiveacquisitioncostcwhichissmall

enough,Rstrictlypreferstoendupinthefullyseparatingequilibrium,andthereforeshewillcommittos2.Insuchacase,

theprominenceoftheoutcomeoffullseparationisrestored.

Letusendthisdiscussionwithamoregeneralpointregardingtheactionsthatthereceivercanmaketofacilitate

commu-nication.Totheextentthatinformationtransmissionisvaluabletothereceiver,itisreasonabletoexpectthatthereceiver

acts(andevenincurscosts)inordertofacilitatetheemergenceofafullyseparatingequilibrium.Ifpubliccommitmenttothe

acquisitionofthesignalispossibleoriftheacquisitioncanbemadebeforethesignalissent,thenseparationisactuallythe

mostprominentoutcome.Buthowlikelyitisthatthisisthecase?Forthesignaltobeeffectivelyacquiredbeforethesender

sendsit,wemustbeinasituationwherethesenderandthereceivercommunicatethroughachannelthatthereceivercan

“switchon”atherwillandwhoseon/offstatusiseasilyobservable(i.e.,atnocost)bythesender.Inaddition,asthecostof

keepingthechannelswitchedonreasonablydependsonhowlongitisleftinsuchastate,anothercrucialrequirementisthat

thereceivermustknowapproximatelywhenthesenderisgoingtosendthesignal,otherwiseanothercoordinationproblem

arises.Whilethissetupcertainlyfitssomerealcasesofsignaling,ithardlyfitsmostofthem.Whensignalacquisitiontakes

theformofbuyingthenecessary“hearing”tools,orwhenittakestheformofmovingtothecorrect“listening”location,

thenpubliccommitmentsoundsreasonable.However,ifsignalacquisitionisamatterofcognitiveeffortorattention,then

thepossibilityofpubliccommitmentseemsfarlesslikely,especiallyforwhatconcernslettingthesenderknowaboutthe

commitment.

7. Conclusions

InProposition1wehaveshownthatinaSCASgamethepresenceofcoststoacquirethesignalrestrictsthefeasibilityof

poolingequilibriatothosewhereallsender’stypespoolontheminimumsignal,whileintheassociatedSFASgamethere

canbepoolingequilibriaonnon-minimumsignals;furthermore,anyseparatingequilibriumoftheSFASgameexistsinthe

SCASgameaswellifandonlyiftheacquisitioncostisnotlargerthanthevalueofacquiringinformationonthesignalforthe

receiver.Furthermore,thereisnorefinementactingthroughrestrictionsonbeliefsatout-of-equilibriumsignals,orrelying

onplayers’trembleswhenchoosingstrategies,thatcangetridofthepoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignal,asitis

showninPropositions2and3,respectively.ThesefindingssuggestthatinaSCASgameapoolingoutcomeontheminimum

signalismuchmoreprominentthanitisintheassociatedSFASgame,andsuchprominencegrowsintheacquisitioncosts

(attheextreme,noseparatingequilibriumexistsforsufficientlyhighacquisitioncosts).

Isthisgoodorbadnews?Fromawelfareperspective,apoolingequilibriumontheminimumsignalcanleadtoeithera

betterorworseoutcomewithrespecttoanalternativeseparatingequilibrium.Ofcourse,thisistrueforstandardsignaling

gamesaswell,sincethetransmissionofinformationwhichoccursinaseparatingequilibrium–whilesurelybeneficialfor

thereceiver–maywellbedetrimentalforsometypesofthesender.Ontopofthis,westressthatinthepresenceofcosts

toacquirethesignal,apoolingequilibriumwherethereceiverexertsnoeffortinsignalacquisitionallowstosavethecosts

16WestressthatifRisnotforcedtocommit,buthasjusttheoptiontodoso,themainthrustoftheargumentstillapplies.Thereasonisthat,aslongas

(10)

ofinformationacquisition.Withoutfurtherassumptionsontherelationshipbetweensender’stypesandreceiver’sactions,

itremainsundecidedwhethersuppressinginformationbutsavingininformationacquisitionisdesirableornot.

Acknowledgements

Thecurrentversionofthepapergreatlyimprovesontheoriginalworkingpaperversionthankstothevaluableindications

oftheCo-Editor(FriederikeMengel),aswellasthepreciouscommentsofanAssociateEditorandthreereferees,whohave

urgedustoincludetherobustnessanalysisagainstplayers’trembles,andSection6.1.WealsowanttothankGeorgeMailath

forinsightfulcommentswhichhavemotivatedtheadditionofSection6.3,andanadvisoryeditorforhavinginspiredSection

6.4.Also,wethankHeskiBar-Isaac,StefanoComino,AndreaGallice,andAntonioNicolò,aswellasallthepeoplewho

haveprovidedusefulcommentsduringthe2014G.R.A.S.S.workshophostedbyCollegioCarloAlbertoandthe2014EARIE

conferencehostedbyBocconiUniversity.WedeclarethatwehavereceivedsupportfromtheItalianMinistryofEducation,

UniversitiesandResearchunderPRINproject2012Z53REX“TheEconomicsofIntuitionandReasoning:a StudyOnthe

ChangeofRationalAttitudesunderTwoElaborationSystems(SOCRATES)”.

AppendixA. Supplementarydata

Supplementary data associated with this article can be found, in the online version, at

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2017.10.022.

References

Alós-Ferrer,C.,Ritzberger,K.,2013.Largeextensiveformgames.Econ.Theory52(1),75–102.

Argenziano,R.,Severinov,S.,Squintani,F.,2014.StrategicInformationAcquisitionandTransmission.TechnicalReport,WorkingPaper.Universityof Essex,UnversityofBritishColumbia,andUniversityofWarwick.

Banks,J.S.,Sobel,J.,1987.Equilibriumselectioninsignalinggames.Econometrica55(3),647–661.

Bester,H.,Ritzberger,K.,2001.Strategicpricing,signalling,andcostlyinformationacquisition.Int.J.Ind.Organ.19(9),1347–1361. Bilancini,E.,Boncinelli,L.,2016a.Rationalattitudechangebyreferencecueswheninformationelaborationrequireseffort.mimeo. Bilancini,E.,Boncinelli,L.,2016b.Signalingtoanalogicalreasonerswhocancostlyacquireinformation.mimeo.

Blackwell,D.,etal.,1951.Comparisonofexperiments.In:ProceedingsoftheSecondBerkeleySymposiumonMathematicalStatisticsandProbability.The RegentsoftheUniversityofCalifornia.

Blackwell,D.,etal.,1953.Equivalentcomparisonsofexperiments.Ann.Math.Stat.24(2),265–272.

Brocas,I.,Carrillo,J.D.,Palfrey,T.R.,2012.Informationgatekeepers:theoryandexperimentalevidence.Econ.Theory51(3),649–676.

Caplin,A.,Dean,M.,2014.RevealedPreference,RationalInattention,andCostlyInformationAcquisition.TechnicalReport.NationalBureauofEconomic Research.

Chen,Y.,Gordon,S.,2015.Informationtransmissioninnestedsender-receivergames.Econ.Theory58(3),543–569. Cho,I.-K.,Kreps,D.M.,1987.Signalinggamesandstableequilibria.Q.J.Econ.102(2),179–221.

Colombo,L.,Femminis,G.,Pavan,A.,2014.Informationacquisitionandwelfare.Rev.Econ.Stud.81(October(4)),1438–1483. Crawford,V.P.,Sobel,J.,1982.Strategicinformationtransmission.Econometrica,1431–1451.

Denti,T.,2016.GamesWithUnrestrictedInformationAcquisition.TechnicalReport,TechnicalReport.MIT. Dewatripont,M.,Tirole,J.,2005.Modesofcommunication.J.Polit.Econ.113(6),1217–1238.

Elmes,S.,Reny,P.J.,1994.Onthestrategicequivalenceofextensiveformgames.J.Econ.Theory62(1),1–23. Es ˝o,P.,Wallace,C.,2014.Informationandevidenceinbargaining.Econ.TheoryBull.2(1),23–32.

Gabaix,X.,Laibson,D.,Moloche,G.,Weinberg,S.,2006.Costlyinformationacquisition:experimentalanalysisofaboundedlyrationalmodel.Am.Econ. Rev.,1043–1068.

Gertz,C.,2014.QualityUncertaintyWithImperfectInformationAcquisition.InstituteofMathematicalEconomicsWorkingPaper(487). Grossman,S.J.,Stiglitz,J.E.,1980.Ontheimpossibilityofinformationallyefficientmarkets.Am.Econ.Rev.70(3),393–408.

Kahneman,D.,2003.Mapsofboundedrationality:psychologyforbehavioraleconomics.Am.Econ.Rev.93(5),1449–1475.

Kohlberg,E.,1981.Someproblemswiththeconceptofperfectequilibrium.In:NBERConferenceonTheoryofGeneralEconomicEquilibrium.University ofCalifornia,Berkeley.

Kohlberg,E.,Mertens,J.-F.,1986.Onthestrategicstabilityofequilibria.Econometrica,1003–1037. Liu,Q.,2011.Informationacquisitionandreputationdynamics.Rev.Econ.Stud.78(4),1400–1425.

Mailath,G.J.,Okuno-Fujiwara,M.,Postlewaite,A.,1993.Belief-basedrefinementsinsignallinggames.J.Econ.Theory60(2),241–276. Martin,D.,2015.StrategicPricingandRationalInattentiontoQuality,AvailableatSSRN2393037.

Menichini,A.M.C.,Simmons,P.J.,2014.Sortingthegoodguysfrombad:ontheoptimalauditstructurewithex-anteinformationacquisition.Econ.Theory 57(2),339–376.

Morath,F.,Münster,J.,2013.Informationacquisitioninconflicts.Econ.Theory54(1),99–129. Myerson,R.B.,1978.Refinementsofthenashequilibriumconcept.Int.J.GameTheory7(2),73–80. Okada,A.,1981.Onstabilityofperfectequilibriumpoints.Int.J.GameTheory10(2),67–73. Oliveros,S.,2013.Abstention,ideologyandinformationacquisition.J.Econ.Theory148(3),871–902. Reis,R.,2006.Inattentiveproducers.Rev.Econ.Stud.73(3),793–821.

Riley,J.G.,2001.Silversignals:twenty-fiveyearsofscreeningandsignaling.J.Econ.Lit.39(2),432–478.

Selten,R.,1975.Reexaminationoftheperfectnessconceptforequilibriumpointsinextensivegames.Int.J.GameTheory4(1),25–55. Shi,X.,2012.Optimalauctionswithinformationacquisition.GamesEcon.Behav.74(2),666–686.

Shimizu,T.,Ishida,J.,2015.Cheaptalkwithaninformedreceiver.Econ.TheoryBull.,1–15.

Sobel,J.,2009.Signalinggames.EncyclopediaofComplexityandSystemsScience,vol.19.,pp.8125–8139. Solan,E.,Yariv,L.,2004.Gameswithespionage.GamesEcon.Behav.47(1),172–199.

Spence,M.,1973.Jobmarketsignaling.Q.J.Econ.87(3),355–374.

Thompson,F.,1952.Equivalenceofgamesinextensiveform.In:RANDTechnicalReport. VanDamme,E.,1991.StabilityandPerfectionofNashEquilibria,vol.339.Springer.

Wen-Tsun,W.,Jia-He,J.,1962.Essentialequilibriumpointsofn-personnon-cooperativegames.Sci.Sin.11(10),1307–1322. Yang,M.,2015.Coordinationwithflexibleinformationacquisition.J.Econ.Theory158,721–738.

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

In [15] several periodic orbits of the Newtonian N -body problem have been found as minimizers of the Lagrangian action in suitable sets of T -periodic loops, for a given T &gt;

SMEunited declared it was open to negotiate a Recommendation concerning minimum wages after the second stage consultation of European Social Partners. SMEs now stand ready

following Daveri and Tabellini (2000) and Irmen and Wigger (2002), rather than Corneo and Marquardt (2000), and then assuming the productivity parameter in the

A map of the pollution levels of PFAS as a sum (limit 10 ng L −1 ) and the selected point sources present in the studied area: (a) industrial sites and (b) waste water treatment....

To better understand the interactions between the rock matrix (damage zones) and the in fluence of pore fluids and pressure fluctuations, we have developed a suite of experiments to

The rule for assigning the prize in the group is as follows: (i) If for one or more players of the group, the guess coincides with the total number of tokens distributed in the

In Chapter 2, we have seen a classic result in Ramsey Theory: Hindman Theorem on finite sums,..