• Non ci sono risultati.

Infinite combinatorics

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Infinite combinatorics"

Copied!
280
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

Infinite combinatorics

(2)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Sets x , y are disjoint if x ∩ y = ∅.

Remark. Let X be a set of cardinality κ (for example κ itself). Let A be a family of pairwise disjoint subsets of X . How many members can A contain?

A family of disjoint subsets of a set of cardinality κ has cardinalty at most κ.

In fact there exists a maximal disjoint family A of cardinality κ: working on X = κ × κ, let A = {Aα| α < κ} where

Aα= {(α, β) ∈ κ × κ | β < κ}. Since S A = κ, family A is maximal. What if we weaken the condition of disjointness?

(3)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Sets x , y are disjoint if x ∩ y = ∅.

Remark. Let X be a set of cardinality κ (for example κ itself). Let A be a family of pairwise disjoint subsets of X . How many members can A contain?

A family of disjoint subsets of a set of cardinality κ has cardinalty at most κ.

In fact there exists a maximal disjoint family A of cardinality κ: working on X = κ × κ, let A = {Aα| α < κ} where

Aα= {(α, β) ∈ κ × κ | β < κ}. Since S A = κ, family A is maximal. What if we weaken the condition of disjointness?

(4)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Sets x , y are disjoint if x ∩ y = ∅.

Remark. Let X be a set of cardinality κ (for example κ itself). Let A be a family of pairwise disjoint subsets of X . How many members can A contain?

A family of disjoint subsets of a set of cardinality κ has cardinalty at most κ.

In fact there exists a maximal disjoint family A of cardinality κ:

working on X = κ × κ, let A = {Aα| α < κ} where

Aα= {(α, β) ∈ κ × κ | β < κ}. Since S A = κ, family A is maximal. What if we weaken the condition of disjointness?

(5)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Sets x , y are disjoint if x ∩ y = ∅.

Remark. Let X be a set of cardinality κ (for example κ itself). Let A be a family of pairwise disjoint subsets of X . How many members can A contain?

A family of disjoint subsets of a set of cardinality κ has cardinalty at most κ.

In fact there exists a maximal disjoint family A of cardinality κ: working on X = κ × κ, let A = {Aα| α < κ} where

Aα= {(α, β) ∈ κ × κ | β < κ}.

SinceS A = κ, family A is maximal. What if we weaken the condition of disjointness?

(6)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Sets x , y are disjoint if x ∩ y = ∅.

Remark. Let X be a set of cardinality κ (for example κ itself). Let A be a family of pairwise disjoint subsets of X . How many members can A contain?

A family of disjoint subsets of a set of cardinality κ has cardinalty at most κ.

In fact there exists a maximal disjoint family A of cardinality κ: working on X = κ × κ, let A = {Aα| α < κ} where

Aα= {(α, β) ∈ κ × κ | β < κ}. Since S A = κ, family A is maximal.

What if we weaken the condition of disjointness?

(7)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Sets x , y are disjoint if x ∩ y = ∅.

Remark. Let X be a set of cardinality κ (for example κ itself). Let A be a family of pairwise disjoint subsets of X . How many members can A contain?

A family of disjoint subsets of a set of cardinality κ has cardinalty at most κ.

In fact there exists a maximal disjoint family A of cardinality κ: working on X = κ × κ, let A = {Aα| α < κ} where

Aα= {(α, β) ∈ κ × κ | β < κ}. Since S A = κ, family A is maximal.

What if we weaken the condition of disjointness?

(8)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Let κ be an infinite cardinal, x , y ⊆ κ. Then x , y are almost disjoint (a.d.) if |x ∩ y | < κ.

An almost disjoint family is some A ⊆ P(κ) such that:

I ∀x ∈ A |x| = κ

I ∀x, y ∈ A (x 6= y ⇒ |x ∩ y | < κ)

A maximal almost disjoint (m.a.d.) family is an ad family A such that for no ad family B one has A ⊂ B.

(9)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Let κ be an infinite cardinal, x , y ⊆ κ. Then x , y are almost disjoint (a.d.) if |x ∩ y | < κ.

An almost disjoint family is some A ⊆ P(κ) such that:

I ∀x ∈ A |x| = κ

I ∀x, y ∈ A (x 6= y ⇒ |x ∩ y | < κ)

A maximal almost disjoint (m.a.d.) family is an ad family A such that for no ad family B one has A ⊂ B.

(10)

Almost disjointness

Definition

Let κ be an infinite cardinal, x , y ⊆ κ. Then x , y are almost disjoint (a.d.) if |x ∩ y | < κ.

An almost disjoint family is some A ⊆ P(κ) such that:

I ∀x ∈ A |x| = κ

I ∀x, y ∈ A (x 6= y ⇒ |x ∩ y | < κ)

A maximal almost disjoint (m.a.d.) family is an ad family A such that for no ad family B one has A ⊂ B.

(11)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ= Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ. Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(12)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A.

Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let Bξ= Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ. Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(13)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}.

Let Bξ= Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ. Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(14)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ = Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη).

So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ. Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(15)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ = Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ.

Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(16)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ = Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ.

Let bξ ∈ Bξ.

Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(17)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ = Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ.

Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct.

So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(18)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ = Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ.

Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ.

Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(19)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ = Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ.

Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ.

Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(20)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ = Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ.

Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(21)

Almost disjointness

Theorem

Let κ be regular. Then:

1. If A ⊆ P(κ) is an ad family with |A| = κ, then A is not maximal 2. There is a mad family B ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality ≥ κ+

Proof.

(1) It is proved that there is some D ⊆ κ, D /∈ A such that D is a.d. with all elements of A. Let A = {Aξ | ξ < κ}. Let

Bξ = Aξ\S

η<ξAη = Aξ\S

η<ξ(Aξ∩ Aη). So Bξ6= ∅ by regularity of κ.

Let bξ ∈ Bξ. Since the Bξ are pairwise disjoint, the bξ are all distinct. So D = {bξ| ξ < κ} has cardinality κ. Finally, if bξ ∈ Aη then η ≥ ξ. Thus D ∩ Aη⊆ {bξ | ξ ≤ η} has cardinality less than κ.

(2) Let A ⊆ P(κ) be an a.d. family of cardinality κ (for example a disjoint family). By Zorn’s lemma, let B a m.a.d.f. with A ⊆ B. By part (1), |B| > κ.

(22)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ.

In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ, then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ. For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X . So |AX| = κ. Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}. This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ. Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(23)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ. In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ,

then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ. For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X . So |AX| = κ. Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}. This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ. Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(24)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ. In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ, then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ. For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X . So |AX| = κ. Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}. This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ. Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(25)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ. In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ, then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ.

For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X . So |AX| = κ. Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}. This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ. Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(26)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ. In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ, then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ. For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X .

So |AX| = κ. Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}. This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ. Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(27)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ. In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ, then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ. For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X . So |AX| = κ.

Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}. This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ. Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(28)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ. In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ, then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ. For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X . So |AX| = κ. Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX ∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}.

This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ. Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(29)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ. In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ, then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ. For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X . So |AX| = κ. Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX ∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}. This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ.

Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(30)

Almost disjointness

So under GCH any m.a.d. family in P(κ) has cardinality κ+= 2κ. In general, the following holds:

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. If 2= κ, then there is an ad family A ⊆ P(κ) of cardinality 2κ.

This holds, for example, for κ = ω; or for κ = ω1 under CH.

Proof.

Let I = {x ⊆ κ | sup x < κ}. So, |I | = κ, as 2= κ. For any X ⊆ κ with |X | = κ, let AX = {X ∩ α | α < κ} be the family of initial cuts of X . So |AX| = κ. Moreover, suppose X 6= Y and let β be an element belonging to exactly one of the two sets. Then

AX ∩ AY ⊆ {X ∩ α | α ≤ β}. This means that

A = {AX | X ⊆ κ ∧ |X | = κ} is an a.d. family of subsets of I of cardinality 2κ. Trasferring this to κ via a bijection I → κ, one gets the assertion.

(31)

Almost disjointness: independent statements

In the theorem, the hypothesis 2= κ, used to grant that |I | = κ, which allowed to work on |I | instead of κ, cannot be dropped. For example, the existence of an a.d. family in P(ω1) of cardinality 2ω1 is independent of ZFC .

A somehow dual question:

Suppose 2κ> κ+. Is there a m.a.d. family of cardinality κ+? This too is independent of ZFC. This is related to Martin’s axiom.

(32)

Almost disjointness: independent statements

In the theorem, the hypothesis 2= κ, used to grant that |I | = κ, which allowed to work on |I | instead of κ, cannot be dropped. For example, the existence of an a.d. family in P(ω1) of cardinality 2ω1 is independent of ZFC .

A somehow dual question:

Suppose 2κ> κ+. Is there a m.a.d. family of cardinality κ+?

This too is independent of ZFC. This is related to Martin’s axiom.

(33)

Almost disjointness: independent statements

In the theorem, the hypothesis 2= κ, used to grant that |I | = κ, which allowed to work on |I | instead of κ, cannot be dropped. For example, the existence of an a.d. family in P(ω1) of cardinality 2ω1 is independent of ZFC .

A somehow dual question:

Suppose 2κ> κ+. Is there a m.a.d. family of cardinality κ+? This too is independent of ZFC. This is related to Martin’s axiom.

(34)

Quasi-disjointness

Another weakening of disjointness is quasi-disjointness.

Definition

A family A of sets is quasi-disjoint, or a ∆-system, if there is a fixed set r , called the root of the ∆-system, such that

∀a, b ∈ A (a 6= b ⇒ a ∩ b = r ).

(35)

The ∆-system lemma

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal.

Let θ > κ be regular and such that

∀λ < θ λ< θ. If |A| ≥ θ and ∀x ∈ A |x | < κ, there there is B ⊆ A such that |B| = θ and B is a ∆-system.

For instance: let κ = ω, θ = ω1. Then:

Corollary

If A is an uncountable family of finite sets, there is an uncountable

∆-system B ⊆ A.

Exercise. Give a direct proof of this corollary.

(36)

The ∆-system lemma

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Let θ > κ be regular and such

that

∀λ < θ λ< θ. If |A| ≥ θ and ∀x ∈ A |x | < κ, there there is B ⊆ A such that |B| = θ and B is a ∆-system.

For instance: let κ = ω, θ = ω1. Then:

Corollary

If A is an uncountable family of finite sets, there is an uncountable

∆-system B ⊆ A.

Exercise. Give a direct proof of this corollary.

(37)

The ∆-system lemma

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Let θ > κ be regular and such that

∀λ < θ λ< θ.

If |A| ≥ θ and ∀x ∈ A |x | < κ, there there is B ⊆ A such that |B| = θ and B is a ∆-system.

For instance: let κ = ω, θ = ω1. Then:

Corollary

If A is an uncountable family of finite sets, there is an uncountable

∆-system B ⊆ A.

Exercise. Give a direct proof of this corollary.

(38)

The ∆-system lemma

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Let θ > κ be regular and such that

∀λ < θ λ< θ. If |A| ≥ θ and ∀x ∈ A |x | < κ,

there there is B ⊆ A such that |B| = θ and B is a ∆-system.

For instance: let κ = ω, θ = ω1. Then:

Corollary

If A is an uncountable family of finite sets, there is an uncountable

∆-system B ⊆ A.

Exercise. Give a direct proof of this corollary.

(39)

The ∆-system lemma

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Let θ > κ be regular and such that

∀λ < θ λ< θ. If |A| ≥ θ and ∀x ∈ A |x | < κ, there there is B ⊆ A such that |B| = θ and B is a ∆-system.

For instance: let κ = ω, θ = ω1. Then:

Corollary

If A is an uncountable family of finite sets, there is an uncountable

∆-system B ⊆ A.

Exercise. Give a direct proof of this corollary.

(40)

The ∆-system lemma

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Let θ > κ be regular and such that

∀λ < θ λ< θ. If |A| ≥ θ and ∀x ∈ A |x | < κ, there there is B ⊆ A such that |B| = θ and B is a ∆-system.

For instance: let κ = ω, θ = ω1. Then:

Corollary

If A is an uncountable family of finite sets, there is an uncountable

∆-system B ⊆ A.

Exercise. Give a direct proof of this corollary.

(41)

The ∆-system lemma

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Let θ > κ be regular and such that

∀λ < θ λ< θ. If |A| ≥ θ and ∀x ∈ A |x | < κ, there there is B ⊆ A such that |B| = θ and B is a ∆-system.

For instance: let κ = ω, θ = ω1. Then:

Corollary

If A is an uncountable family of finite sets, there is an uncountable

∆-system B ⊆ A.

Exercise. Give a direct proof of this corollary.

(42)

The ∆-system lemma

Theorem

Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Let θ > κ be regular and such that

∀λ < θ λ< θ. If |A| ≥ θ and ∀x ∈ A |x | < κ, there there is B ⊆ A such that |B| = θ and B is a ∆-system.

For instance: let κ = ω, θ = ω1. Then:

Corollary

If A is an uncountable family of finite sets, there is an uncountable

∆-system B ⊆ A.

Exercise. Give a direct proof of this corollary.

(43)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ,

so that |S A| ≤ θ, so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ). Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ. Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ. The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ. SoS A1 is unbounded in θ. For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

(44)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ, so that |S A| ≤ θ,

so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ). Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ. Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ. The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ. SoS A1 is unbounded in θ. For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

(45)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ, so that |S A| ≤ θ, so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ).

Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ. Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ. The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ. SoS A1 is unbounded in θ. For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

(46)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ, so that |S A| ≤ θ, so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ). Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ.

Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ. The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ. SoS A1 is unbounded in θ. For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

(47)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ, so that |S A| ≤ θ, so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ). Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ. Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ.

It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ. The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ. SoS A1 is unbounded in θ. For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

(48)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ, so that |S A| ≤ θ, so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ). Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ. Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ. The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ. SoS A1 is unbounded in θ. For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

(49)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ, so that |S A| ≤ θ, so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ). Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ. Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ.

The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ. SoS A1 is unbounded in θ. For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

(50)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ, so that |S A| ≤ θ, so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ). Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ. Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ. The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ.

SoS A1 is unbounded in θ. For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

(51)

The ∆-system lemma

Proof.

By shrinking, one can assume |A| = θ, so that |S A| ≤ θ, so that one can also assume |S A| ⊆ θ, i.e. A ⊆ P(θ). Then each x ∈ A has some order type < κ. Since θ is regular and θ > κ, there is ρ < κ such that A1= {x ∈ A | x has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. It is enough to extract the ∆-system from A1.

Fix α < θ. The subsets of α of cardinality less than κ are at most

|α| < θ. SoS A1 is unbounded in θ.

For any x ∈ A1, ξ < ρ, let x (ξ) be the ξ-th element of x . Since θ is regular, there is a least ξ0such that {x(ξ0) | x ∈ A1} is unbounded in θ. Let

α0= sup{x (η) + 1 | x ∈ A1, η < ξ0}. Then α0< θ and

∀x ∈ A1 ∀η < ξ0 x (η) < α0.

Define inductively, for µ < θ, elements xµ∈ A1so that xµ0) is bigger than α0and of all elements of all xν, for ν < µ. Let A2be the collection of such elements. Then |A2| = θ and ∀x, y ∈ A2(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y ⊆ α0). Each x ∩ α0is a subset of α0of cardinality less that κ. Since there are at most |α0|< θ of them, there are r ⊆ α0, B ⊆ A2such that |B| = θ and ∀x ∈ B x ∩ α0= r , which implies ∀x , y ∈ B(x 6= y ⇒ x ∩ y = r ).

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

One specific challenge for establishing if changes in gut microbial composition and/or activity have an effect on human health or biomarkers of human health is that effects on

If H ∩ Q is a couple of κ-defined lines then any κ-defined quadric of the pencil has the rulings defined over κ, using an argument analogous to 5.1.3 each quadric containing at least

alla gestante, deve ritenersi circostanza idonea a porsi in rapporto di casualità con il mancato esercizio, da parte della donna, della facoltà

Our work employs dynamic convolutional filters conditioned on the current instruction to extract the relevant piece of information from the visual perception, which is in turn used

A plausible pathway for the formation of 6a-b consists of a nucleophilic addition at the bridging carbyne carbon, followed by intramolecular displacement of the

Here, we describe the effects of a number of natural antioxidants (polyphenols, carotenoids, and thiolic molecules) in rescuing astrocytic function and neuronal viability following

In [8] the author and Sharma proved that a conformally recurrent Sasakian manifold is locally isometric to a unit sphere S 2n+1 (1).. The manifold M equipped with the structure (η,

In this work we derive the input flux and the integration times for the three channels of SIMBIO-SYS, using the radiometric model to obtain the source radiance for each Mercury