• Non ci sono risultati.

Political Philosophy_ PPE_ CitizenshipTheory

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Political Philosophy_ PPE_ CitizenshipTheory"

Copied!
26
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

Citizenship Theory

(2)

Origins

• Historically, citizenship theories refer to the political experiences of

the ancient Greek polis and the Italian city-states during the

Renaissance. They consider the form citizenship took in the Greek

polis and Italian city-states as a model.

• Philosophically, citizenship theories are formulated in opposition to

classical liberalism. They criticize liberalism for its merely negative

conception of freedom. Instead of a negative conception of freedom,

as non-interference, citizenship theories propose a more active, moral

idea of freedom.

(3)

Main Citizenship Theories

• Founding fathers: Citizenship theories often refer to Aristotle and

Machiavelli for the historical underpinning of their claims. Yet, the

main and most important philosopher for citizenship theories is

undeniably Jean-Jacques Rousseau and his treatise Du contrat social.

The key concept for all citizenship theories is the general will

conceived in opposition to the particular interests of the citizens.

• Today citizenship theories can be divided into two strains:

deliberative democracy and Republicanism. The main theorist of

deliberative democracy is Jürgen Habermas. Important contemporary

Republican theorists are Philip Pettit and Quentin Skinner.

(4)

Kymlicka's interpretation of citizenship

theories

• Kymlicka is not taking the opposition of citizenship theories to

liberalism as the point of departure. He does not discuss the divide

between classical liberalism (Hobbes/Locke) and Republicanism

(Rousseau/Kant) and claims, on the contrary, that citizenship theories

must be read in continuity and not in opposition to liberalism.

• He holds that citizenship theories basically accept the liberal

institutional framework of individual rights, yet criticize the

inadequate motivational sets of liberal citizens. Citizenship theories

maintain that liberalism assures only rights without the adequate

obligations.

(5)

Kymlicka's interpretation (cont.)

• He writes: "Democracy depends, not only on the justice of its basic

institutions, but also on the qualities and attitudes of its citizens" (p. 285). • He considers citizenship theories rather complementary than in opposition

to liberalism. "A theory of citizenship is now widely seen as a necessary supplement to earlier theories of institutional justice" (p. 286). In order that liberalism works, citizens must be virtuous. Habermas: "The

institutions of constitutional freedom are only worth as much as a population makes of them" (p. 285).

• Although almost all contemporary theories of deliberative democracy as much as Republicanism are committed to a basic set of individual rights, you should keep in mind that there is potentially a conflict between the

general will and particular interests (we shall see this in our brief discussion on deliberative democracy later on).

(6)

Traditional theories of citizenship

• In the liberal-democratic tradition, citizenship is defined almost

entirely in terms of the possession of rights. Treating people as full

and equal members of a society requires an increasing number of

citizenship rights.

• T. H. Marshall in Citizenship and Social Class divides citizenship rights

into three categories: civil rights (18th century), political rights (19th

century) and social rights (20th century).

• This is often called 'passive' or 'private' citizenship, because of its

emphasis on passive entitlements, and the absence of any obligation

to participate in public life. In this interpretation, citizenship is "the

right to have rights" (p. 288).

(7)

New conceptions of citizenship

According to William Galston, responsible citizenship requires four

types of civic virtues:

1. General virtues: courage, law-abidingness, loyalty.

2. Social virtues: independence, open-mindedness.

3. Economic virtues: work ethic, capacity to delay self-gratification,

adaptability to economic and technological change.

4. Political virtues: capacity to discern and respect the rights of others,

willingness to demand only what can be paid for, ability to evaluate the

performance of those in office, willingness to engage in public

(8)

The problem

• This clearly sounds very nice on paper (perhaps a little bit less if you are a committed liberal), but how to achieve that people first develop and then cultivate these virtues? How to activate citizens, once we take for granted that virtues are not our natural attitude and that we are rather concerned with the pursuit of happiness and our individual interests?

• Traditional liberal democracies, being based upon an 'aggregative' or 'vote-centered' conception of democracy, have only a very thin legitimacy. An electoral, self-interested majority dominates through the government and its laws a minority without that majoritarian policies have to respect any minimal standards of objectivity (except of course respecting individual rights) or be based upon consensus or compromise.

(9)

The problem (cont.)

• One of the fundamental problems of so-called vote-centric democracies is that citizens have to accept policies with which they may totally disagree. As shows the deep conflicts between Democrats and Republicans in the US, but of course also in Europe (remember the recent irreconcilable conflict between Renzi and the labor unions concerning the Jobs Acts), continuing disagreement can put the welfare of societies at risk.

• Moreover, liberal democracies reproduce solidified power structures and inequalities that undo individual rights and nullify freedom and the

equality of opportunity. That is Rousseau's profound motivation for proposing a new social contract and Republican institutions (see his

analysis of modernity and bourgeois society in Le Discours sur l'origine et

les fondements de l'inégalité parmi les hommes; see also Marx's critique of

(10)

The solution

• The solution is basically found in the traditions of Aristotle, Rousseau and Kant.

• Conceptually, we can distinguish between two highly important solutions: 1. Deliberative Democracy

2. Republicanism

• The two solutions often overlap (such as in the case of Habermas), they must not necessarily do so (see the Republican theory of Philip Pettit). • As we will see in a moment, Aristotle is a complicated reference point for

citizenship theories. Aristotle's theory of the zoon politikon is based upon a very questionable metaphysics of human nature. Accordingly, most

theorists of deliberative democracy and Republicanism have Rousseau and Kant in the background.

(11)

Deliberative democracy: the theory

• Most important reading: Jürgen Habermas (1990), Moral Consciousness

and Communicative Action. For a little bit more accessible introduction see

Amy Gutmann & Dennis Thompson (2004), Why Deliberative Democracy?. • According to the theorem of deliberative democracy or the theory of

discourse ethics, political decisions have to be taken only after processes of deliberation and opinion formation.

• This does contribute to better decisions, "since citizens would test and

discard those assumptions or beliefs which were found in public debate to be wrong or short-sighted or otherwise indefensible" (p. 291).

• Yet, this involves a non-coercive discussion without manipulation, indoctrination, propaganda, deception or threats.

• Deliberative democracy is said to stimulate political participation, in particular among young people and minorities.

(12)

Deliberative democracy: the problems

• The goal of deliberative democracy is to have greater agreement and to

converge on a "common ordering of individual needs and wants into single vision of the future un which all can share" (p. 291).

• Yet, as Kymlicka rightly puts it, deliberating about our differences might not be the same as eliminating our differences. At the end of the day, we might find ourselves we the same hardened oppositions as before.

• More formal and technical problems concern the appropriate forums for deliberation, representation and organizational aspects.

• Yet, The main problem of deliberative democracy is what it should actually achieve. The possible goals could be the following: (1) a simple agreement, (2) more objective, true and just decisions or (3) greater acceptance of

(13)

Deliberative democracy: the main problem

(1) Simple agreement: It is unclear how opposing parties could find an

agreement without a notion of objectivity, truth or morality. Suppose

they are engaged in a process of reason-giving to convince each other

of the respective positions. Why should we accept reasons that we do

not consider to be somehow true or morally required? Moreover,

imagine that they find an agreement at the cost of a third party. Could

such an agreement really be acceptable?

(2) Objectivity, truth and justice: It is unclear to what extent

deliberation brings us closer to truth or morality. If truth or morality are

unknown, we never can say if an agreement is closer to the truth or

not. If, on the other hand, the truth is known (perhaps a priori as in

(14)

Deliberative democracy: the main problem

(cont.)

(3) Acceptance: Deliberation is said to bring about stronger acceptance

of policies, in particular in multicultural societies with minorities. Here

again it is unclear how deliberation could foster acceptance of policies

that we basically consider unjust. The problem is again that

(15)

Republicanism

• Given these problems of deliberative democracies, some propose to

return to the traditional theory of Republicanism.

• We can distinguish between two strains of Republicanism: civic

Republicanism in the vain of Aristotle and Rousseau and liberal

Republicanism.

• Civic Republicanism tries to overcome the problems of deliberative

democracy either by way of a theory of human nature (Aristotle) or

by way of a theory of morality in the tradition of Rousseau's general

will.

(16)

Civic republicanism: the theory

• Aristotle holds a very peculiar metaphysical theory of human nature that, when it comes to politics, can be summarized under the heading of zoon

politikon (political animal). Aristotle thinks that each human being has an

essential core that determines his or her identity and that she needs to realize during life.

• Without going deep into Aristotelean metaphysics, the theory of zoon

politikon must not only establish that individuals need to be politically

active and that political life is the highest life available to us - higher than merely social and private life. It must also show that the ends people have to realize by virtue of their nature are compatible with each other and that the virtuous life not only allows for, but also necessitates the agreement deliberative democracy has so much trouble to find.

(17)

Civic republicanism: the problem

• In terms of a philosophy of history, one might say in the vain of Benjamin Constant that civic republicanism corresponds to the liberty of the ancients but has become incompatible with the liberty of moderns. The ancients

have the value of public life and active participation in the affairs of the

polis. However, moderns value the unimpeded pursuit of happiness. In the course of history, values change and what was once perfectly natural has become obsolete.

• In more conceptual terms, we need to ask if virtues really have their source in our human nature or identity and if by themselves virtuous behavior

guarantees agreement. Since virtues tell us, for example, to be courageous, yet virtues leave it open where we should apply our courage. To be

provocative: suicide bombers are beyond any doubts very courageous, but would we call them just?

(18)

Liberal republicanism: instrumental virtues

• Liberal citizenship generally is seen as simply requiring non-interference

with others. But that, according to Kymlicka, "ignores one of the most basic requirements of liberal citizenship, which is the social virtue of 'civility' or 'decency'" (p. 300). In order that liberalism works, non-interference is not enough, citizens must also display certain virtues.

• "Whether individuals have genuinely equal opportunity depends not only on government actions, but also on the actions of institutions within civil society - corporations, schools, stores, landlords, etc." (p. 301).

• Consider freedom of expression cases: Many commentators claim that the Danish cartoons or Charlie Hebdo violate the principle of civility and

decency. Insulting Muslims, they further prejudices and contribute to their social marginalization, putting the political community as a whole at risk. Although a liberal state clearly cannot legally forbid satire, virtuous citizens should engage in self-restraint.

(19)

Liberal republicanism: the problem

• If it is not a matter of injustice insulting religious, ethnic or sexual

minorities or simply thinking badly of them, how could we be morally

required not do so and, on the contrary, love end embrace them?

• The beauty of liberalism is that it leaves us in peace as long as we do

not interfere with each others' freedom (and what non-interference

is, is of course a matter of debate). We are free to think what we like

without being morally judged.

• For a traditional or classic liberal, such as Isaiah Berlin, liberal

republicanism is unjust. Since it does not leave us free to live the lives

we want to live, as long as we respect the negative freedom of others.

(20)

The seedbeds of civic virtues

• Yet, it is clear that although liberalism has only one moral presupposition, non-interference, the sources of the motivation to respect each others' negative freedom and to display civility and decency might not be very

different. Hence, even liberalism needs to be concerned with some form of moral education.

• Kymlicka individuates and discusses different sources of moral education and their problems:

1. Political participation: Exposes people to new ideas and develops new

identities, yet it does not assure inclusiveness. Marginalizing other could pay off politically.

2. Market: Teaches people the virtues of initiative and self-reliance, but not a sense of justice or social responsibility.

(21)

The seedbeds of civic virtue (cont.)

3. Civil society: Civility can only be learned in the associational networks

of civil society (Michael Walzer), yet civil society might also further

family despotism, deference to authority, intolerance of other faiths

and prejudice against other races, and so on. And a liberal state cannot

intervene in the structure of its civil society, if it does not want to

endanger the motivations that make that civil society exists in the first

place.

4. Family and mothering: Teaches the responsibility to conserve life and

protect the vulnerable, yet it is doubtful if mothering involves the same

attributes or virtues as democratic citizenship.

(22)

The seedbeds of civic virtue (cont.)

5. Schools: Teach how to engage in the kind of critical reasoning and

moral perspective that defines public reasonableness. Yet, this might

put children in opposition to more traditional cultural and religious

groups. This create a huge dilemma for liberals, since liberal education

is anything but value-neutral. Kymlicka concludes that a 'detached

school', in the sense of being detached from the student's home

community or culture, "is unlikely to be effective" (p. 310).

Conclusion: "Citizens learn an overlapping set of virtues from an

overlapping set of institutions" (p. 310).

(23)

The seedbeds of civic virtue (cont.)

• Yet, a sense of justice and civic virtues might not be enough to foster

agreement and accomodation. Liberal nationalists argue that social

unity based upon thin principles of justice must be further satbilized

and strengthened by the development of a shared sense of

(24)

Cosmopolitan citizenship

• Some argue against liberal nationalism that in the wake of

globalization we need more global conceptions of democratic

citizenship. This position is called cosmopolitanism. Democracy has to

transcend national and linguistic barriers in order to not contradict

requirements of justice.

• Consider globalization and market liberalization: The standard

cosmopolitan argument is that since decisions are taken elsewhere,

on the global and not any longer at the national level, justice requires

that democratic constituencies have to be extended, giving rise to

(25)

Cosmopolitan citizenship: the problem

• Kymlicka quotes the case of the EU. In order to increase its democratic

accountability, European citizens prefer strengthening the accountability of their national governments, increasing the power of intrastate EU

institution, such as the European Council, rather than giving more power to the supranational EU institutions, such as the European Parliament and the Commission.

• Kymlicka concludes that transnational citizenship could have negative consequences for democratic citizenship at the domestic level. Shifting power from the Council to the Parliament, in the absence of and with an "absolutely non-existent" prospect for a common European public sphere (mass media, political parties, civil society), would "aggravate rather than solve the problem" of the EU's democratic accountability (Dieter Grimm, p. 315).

(26)

The politics of republicanism

• Kymlicka complains that Republicans only rarely apply their theories to

questions of public policy. Few endorse for example mandatory voting and national service, the abolition of private schools, etc.

• Moreover, it is not clear how urgent the need to promote good citizenship is. Today citizens are more tolerant, respectful of each others' rights,

committed to democracy and constitutionalism, than previous generations. There is a veritable explosion of counter-publics (remember the Occupy

movements around the globe).

• Kymlicka's hypothesis is that under the sociological condition of a great

pluralism of comprehensive doctrines framing questions of justice in terms of citizenship is politically more effective. Theories of citizenship are

instrumental to, and perhaps complementary to, but never substitutes of theories of justice.

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

Abbreviations: PT: Physical Treatment group; CT: Cognitive Treatment group; CTRL: Control group; DCT: Digit Cancellation Test, ADAS-Cog: Cognitive section of the Alzheimer’s

Si credono illustri, ma sono dei poeti da strapazzo (hack poets). È stata una conferenza piuttosto noiosa. Qui si lavora sulla morfologia derivativa e quindi sul significato

sidered a model species for the study of the phenomenon of heterosis. This species is 10), allogamous, monoecious, with separated male and female inflorescences in the

Because of the limited excitation energy, our peripheral sample can be rea- sonably described as a standard Hauser-Feshbach or Weisskopf evaporation from an excited source of mass

The extreme value statistics for frequency analysis of extreme precipitation were performed for Dar Es Salaam (TZ) and Addis Ababa (ET) case studies for both cases of historical

Senza ovviamente andare alla deriva pop-etica che questi argomenti inevitabilmente producono in una società iperinformata, iperascoltata, iperrappresentata, la

Nella sua relazione alla Consulta Devoto, dopo aver ammesso la compresenza nell’ambito del movimento federalista di una corrente più orientata all’approfondimento culturale e

ter asking any questions they might have, they then go through a training set of 25 galaxies. These 25 galaxies were chosen to reflect the wide range of different clas- sifications