• Non ci sono risultati.

Standard universal dendrites as small Polish structures

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Standard universal dendrites as small Polish structures"

Copied!
71
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

Standard universal dendrites as small Polish structures

(2)

The concept of small Polish structures has been introduced and studied in K. Krupi´ nski, Some model theory of Polish structures, TAMS

Goals:

▸ Provide a setting which allows simultaneous application of ideas and techniques from model theory and descriptive set theory.

In particular:

▸ prove counterparts of some results from stability theory;

▸ find, in this wider context, counterexamples to open problems;

▸ provide a (yet another) tool to measure complexity of dinamycal

systems.

(3)

The concept of small Polish structures has been introduced and studied in K. Krupi´ nski, Some model theory of Polish structures, TAMS

Goals:

▸ Provide a setting which allows simultaneous application of ideas and techniques from model theory and descriptive set theory.

In particular:

▸ prove counterparts of some results from stability theory;

▸ find, in this wider context, counterexamples to open problems;

▸ provide a (yet another) tool to measure complexity of dinamycal

systems.

(4)

The concept of small Polish structures has been introduced and studied in K. Krupi´ nski, Some model theory of Polish structures, TAMS

Goals:

▸ Provide a setting which allows simultaneous application of ideas and techniques from model theory and descriptive set theory.

In particular:

▸ prove counterparts of some results from stability theory;

▸ find, in this wider context, counterexamples to open problems;

▸ provide a (yet another) tool to measure complexity of dinamycal

systems.

(5)

The concept of small Polish structures has been introduced and studied in K. Krupi´ nski, Some model theory of Polish structures, TAMS

Goals:

▸ Provide a setting which allows simultaneous application of ideas and techniques from model theory and descriptive set theory.

In particular:

▸ prove counterparts of some results from stability theory;

▸ find, in this wider context, counterexamples to open problems;

▸ provide a (yet another) tool to measure complexity of dinamycal

systems.

(6)

The concept of small Polish structures has been introduced and studied in K. Krupi´ nski, Some model theory of Polish structures, TAMS

Goals:

▸ Provide a setting which allows simultaneous application of ideas and techniques from model theory and descriptive set theory.

In particular:

▸ prove counterparts of some results from stability theory;

▸ find, in this wider context, counterexamples to open problems;

▸ provide a (yet another) tool to measure complexity of dinamycal

systems.

(7)

Polish structures

A Polish structure is a pair (X , G) where:

▸ G is a Polish group acting faithfully on a set X i.e ∀g, g ∈ G (g ≠ g ⇒ ∃a ∈ X ga ≠ g a )

▸ the stabilisers of all singletons are closed

This generalises the notion of a profinite structure.

Notation: For A ⊆ X , G A will denote the pointwise stabiliser of A.

(8)

Polish structures

A Polish structure is a pair (X , G) where:

▸ G is a Polish group acting faithfully on a set X i.e ∀g, g ∈ G (g ≠ g ⇒ ∃a ∈ X ga ≠ g a )

▸ the stabilisers of all singletons are closed This generalises the notion of a profinite structure.

Notation: For A ⊆ X , G A will denote the pointwise stabiliser of A.

(9)

Polish structures

A Polish structure is a pair (X , G) where:

▸ G is a Polish group acting faithfully on a set X i.e ∀g, g ∈ G (g ≠ g ⇒ ∃a ∈ X ga ≠ g a )

▸ the stabilisers of all singletons are closed This generalises the notion of a profinite structure.

Notation: For A ⊆ X , G A will denote the pointwise stabiliser of A.

(10)

Independence

A notion of independence in Polish structures is introduce.

Let ⃗a ∈ X and A ⊆ B ⊆ X finite.

The idea is to say that ⃗a is independent from B over A if, once A has been fixed, asking to fix B does not add too much constraint on ⃗a, i.e.

G B ⃗a is big in G A ⃗a.

(11)

Some topological notions of bigness: Open, non-meagre,...

However:

● X does not necessarily have a topology.

● Even if X has a nice topology, some orbits G A ⃗a might behave badly, like being meagre in themselves.

Thus the relations of independence are defined via a pull back to the

group G .

(12)

Some topological notions of bigness: Open, non-meagre,...

However:

● X does not necessarily have a topology.

● Even if X has a nice topology, some orbits G A ⃗a might behave badly, like being meagre in themselves.

Thus the relations of independence are defined via a pull back to the

group G .

(13)

Some topological notions of bigness: Open, non-meagre,...

However:

● X does not necessarily have a topology.

● Even if X has a nice topology, some orbits G A ⃗a might behave badly, like being meagre in themselves.

Thus the relations of independence are defined via a pull back to the

group G .

(14)

Some topological notions of bigness: Open, non-meagre,...

However:

● X does not necessarily have a topology.

● Even if X has a nice topology, some orbits G A ⃗a might behave badly, like being meagre in themselves.

Thus the relations of independence are defined via a pull back to the

group G .

(15)

Let π A ∶ G A → G A ⃗a and check whether g ↦ g⃗a

π −1 A (G B ⃗a) is big in π −1 A (G A ⃗a) = G A .

Definitions.

Let ⃗a ∈ X and A, B ⊆ fin X (most often A ⊆ B).

⃗a ⌣∣ o A B: ⃗a is o-independent from B over A if π A −1 (G A∪B ⃗a) is open in G A

(written π −1 A (G A∪B ⃗a) ⊆ o G A ).

⃗a ⌣∣ nm A B: ⃗a is nm-independent from B over A if π −1 A (G A∪B ⃗a) is non-meagre in G A (written π A −1 (G A∪B ⃗a) ⊆ nm G A ).

Remark. If X is separable metrisable, the action G × X → X is continuous and G A ⃗a is not meagre in itself, then

⃗a A B ⇔ G A∪B ⃗a ⊆ G A ⃗a

(for ∗ = nm it is enough X being Hausdorff)

(16)

Let π A ∶ G A → G A ⃗a and check whether g ↦ g⃗a

π −1 A (G B ⃗a) is big in π −1 A (G A ⃗a) = G A . Definitions.

Let ⃗a ∈ X and A, B ⊆ fin X (most often A ⊆ B).

⃗a ⌣∣ o A B: ⃗a is o-independent from B over A if π A −1 (G A∪B ⃗a) is open in G A

(written π −1 A (G A∪B ⃗a) ⊆ o G A ).

⃗a ⌣∣ nm A B: ⃗a is nm-independent from B over A if π −1 A (G A∪B ⃗a) is non-meagre in G A (written π A −1 (G A∪B ⃗a) ⊆ nm G A ).

Remark. If X is separable metrisable, the action G × X → X is continuous and G A ⃗a is not meagre in itself, then

⃗a A B ⇔ G A∪B ⃗a ⊆ G A ⃗a

(for ∗ = nm it is enough X being Hausdorff)

(17)

Let π A ∶ G A → G A ⃗a and check whether g ↦ g⃗a

π −1 A (G B ⃗a) is big in π −1 A (G A ⃗a) = G A . Definitions.

Let ⃗a ∈ X and A, B ⊆ fin X (most often A ⊆ B).

⃗a ⌣∣ o A B: ⃗a is o-independent from B over A if π A −1 (G A∪B ⃗a) is open in G A

(written π −1 A (G A∪B ⃗a) ⊆ o G A ).

⃗a ⌣∣ nm A B: ⃗a is nm-independent from B over A if π −1 A (G A∪B ⃗a) is non-meagre in G A (written π A −1 (G A∪B ⃗a) ⊆ nm G A ).

Remark. If X is separable metrisable, the action G × X → X is continuous and G A ⃗a is not meagre in itself, then

⃗a A B ⇔ G A∪B ⃗a ⊆ G A ⃗a

(for ∗ = nm it is enough X being Hausdorff)

(18)

Example: A = ∅.

⃗a ⌣∣ B iff {g ∈ G ∣ ∃h ∈ G B g ⃗a = h⃗a} ⊆ G

The opposite situation: small orbits. Let A ⊆ fin X .

▸ dcl (A) = {a ∈ X ∣ G A a = {a}}: definable closure of A

▸ acl (A) = {a ∈ X ∣ G A a is finite }: strong algebraic closure of A

▸ Acl (A) = {a ∈ X ∣ G A a is at most countable }: algebraic closure of A For any A ⊆ X , define

dcl (A) = ⋃

A

0

fin

X

dcl (A 0 ),

etc.

(19)

Example: A = ∅.

⃗a ⌣∣ B iff {g ∈ G ∣ ∃h ∈ G B g ⃗a = h⃗a} ⊆ G The opposite situation: small orbits. Let A ⊆ fin X .

▸ dcl (A) = {a ∈ X ∣ G A a = {a}}: definable closure of A

▸ acl (A) = {a ∈ X ∣ G A a is finite }: strong algebraic closure of A

▸ Acl (A) = {a ∈ X ∣ G A a is at most countable }: algebraic closure of A For any A ⊆ X , define

dcl (A) = ⋃

A

0

fin

X

dcl (A 0 ),

etc.

(20)

Basic properties of independence

To develop a counterpart of basic geometric stability theory, five properties of the independence relation are needed

▸ Invariance: ⃗a ⌣∣ A B ⇔ g⃗a ⌣∣ gA gB

▸ Simmetry: ⃗a ⌣∣ A ⃗b ⇔ ⃗b ⌣∣ A ⃗a

▸ Transitivity: ⃗a ⌣∣ A B ∧ ⃗a ⌣∣ B C ⇔ ⃗a ⌣∣ A C

▸ a ∈ Acl(A) ⇔ ∀B ⃗a ⌣∣ A B

▸ Existence of independent extensions

(21)

Small Polish structures

A Polish structure (X , G) is small if

∀n, G × X n → X n has at most countably many orbits

(iff ∀a 1 , . . . , a n ∈ X , G a

1

,...,a

n

× X → X has at most countably many orbits)

(22)

Small Polish structures

A Polish structure (X , G) is small if

∀n, G × X n → X n has at most countably many orbits

(iff ∀a 1 , . . . , a n ∈ X , G a

1

,...,a

n

× X → X has at most countably many orbits)

(23)

Existence of independent extensions

Theorem. Let (X , G) be a small Polish structure. Then

∀⃗a, ∀A ⊆ B ⊆ fin X ,

∃⃗b ∈ G A ⃗a such that

⃗b ⌣∣ nm A B

Remark. The same is not true for o-independent extensions.

(24)

Existence of independent extensions

Theorem. Let (X , G) be a small Polish structure. Then

∀⃗a, ∀A ⊆ B ⊆ fin X , ∃⃗b ∈ G A ⃗a

such that

⃗b ⌣∣ nm A B

Remark. The same is not true for o-independent extensions.

(25)

Existence of independent extensions

Theorem. Let (X , G) be a small Polish structure. Then

∀⃗a, ∀A ⊆ B ⊆ fin X , ∃⃗b ∈ G A ⃗a such that

⃗b ⌣∣ nm A B

Remark. The same is not true for o-independent extensions.

(26)

Existence of independent extensions

Theorem. Let (X , G) be a small Polish structure. Then

∀⃗a, ∀A ⊆ B ⊆ fin X , ∃⃗b ∈ G A ⃗a such that

⃗b ⌣∣ nm A B

Remark. The same is not true for o-independent extensions.

(27)

Adaptation of some concepts from stability theory

▸ X eq = ⋃{X n /E ∣E invariant eq. rel. on X n , s.t Stab ([a] E ) ≤ c G }, the imaginary extension of X

▸ Sets X n /E are the sorts of X eq

▸ D ⊆ X n /E, for X n /E a sort, is definable on A ⊆ fin X eq if G A D = D and Stab (D) ≤ c G

▸ d ∈ X eq is a name for D if ∀g ∈ G (gD = D ⇔ gd = d)

Proposition. Every definable set in X eq has a name in X eq .

(28)

Adaptation of some concepts from stability theory

▸ X eq = ⋃{X n /E ∣E invariant eq. rel. on X n , s.t Stab ([a] E ) ≤ c G }, the imaginary extension of X

▸ Sets X n /E are the sorts of X eq

▸ D ⊆ X n /E, for X n /E a sort, is definable on A ⊆ fin X eq if G A D = D and Stab (D) ≤ c G

▸ d ∈ X eq is a name for D if ∀g ∈ G (gD = D ⇔ gd = d)

Proposition. Every definable set in X eq has a name in X eq .

(29)

Adaptation of some concepts from stability theory

▸ X eq = ⋃{X n /E ∣E invariant eq. rel. on X n , s.t Stab ([a] E ) ≤ c G }, the imaginary extension of X

▸ Sets X n /E are the sorts of X eq

▸ D ⊆ X n /E, for X n /E a sort, is definable on A ⊆ fin X eq if G A D = D and Stab (D) ≤ c G

▸ d ∈ X eq is a name for D if ∀g ∈ G (gD = D ⇔ gd = d)

Proposition. Every definable set in X eq has a name in X eq .

(30)

Adaptation of some concepts from stability theory

▸ X eq = ⋃{X n /E ∣E invariant eq. rel. on X n , s.t Stab ([a] E ) ≤ c G }, the imaginary extension of X

▸ Sets X n /E are the sorts of X eq

▸ D ⊆ X n /E, for X n /E a sort, is definable on A ⊆ fin X eq if G A D = D and Stab (D) ≤ c G

▸ d ∈ X eq is a name for D if ∀g ∈ G (gD = D ⇔ gd = d)

Proposition. Every definable set in X eq has a name in X eq .

(31)

Adaptation of some concepts from stability theory

▸ X eq = ⋃{X n /E ∣E invariant eq. rel. on X n , s.t Stab ([a] E ) ≤ c G }, the imaginary extension of X

▸ Sets X n /E are the sorts of X eq

▸ D ⊆ X n /E, for X n /E a sort, is definable on A ⊆ fin X eq if G A D = D and Stab (D) ≤ c G

▸ d ∈ X eq is a name for D if ∀g ∈ G (gD = D ⇔ gd = d)

Proposition. Every definable set in X eq has a name in X eq .

(32)

Adaptation of some concepts from stability theory

▸ X eq = ⋃{X n /E ∣E invariant eq. rel. on X n , s.t Stab ([a] E ) ≤ c G }, the imaginary extension of X

▸ Sets X n /E are the sorts of X eq

▸ D ⊆ X n /E, for X n /E a sort, is definable on A ⊆ fin X eq if G A D = D and Stab (D) ≤ c G

▸ d ∈ X eq is a name for D if ∀g ∈ G (gD = D ⇔ gd = d)

Proposition. Every definable set in X eq has a name in X eq .

(33)

Ranks

Assume (X , G) is a small Polish structure (but in most situations it is enough to ask for the existence of nm-independent extensions)

Definition. N M is the function from the collection of orbits over finite sets (in X or X eq ) to Ord ∪ {∞},

N M ∶ (a, A) ↦ N M(a, A) ∈ Ord ∪ {∞} satisfying

N M(a, A) ≥ α + 1 ⇔ ∃B ⊇ fin A (N M(a, B) ≥ α ∧ ¬a ⌣∣ nm A B )

Example. N M(a, A) = 0 ⇔ a ∈ Acl eq (A).

(34)

Ranks

Assume (X , G) is a small Polish structure (but in most situations it is enough to ask for the existence of nm-independent extensions)

Definition. N M is the function from the collection of orbits over finite sets (in X or X eq ) to Ord ∪ {∞},

N M ∶ (a, A) ↦ N M(a, A) ∈ Ord ∪ {∞}

satisfying

N M(a, A) ≥ α + 1 ⇔ ∃B ⊇ fin A (N M(a, B) ≥ α ∧ ¬a ⌣∣ nm A B )

Example. N M(a, A) = 0 ⇔ a ∈ Acl eq (A).

(35)

Ranks

Assume (X , G) is a small Polish structure (but in most situations it is enough to ask for the existence of nm-independent extensions)

Definition. N M is the function from the collection of orbits over finite sets (in X or X eq ) to Ord ∪ {∞},

N M ∶ (a, A) ↦ N M(a, A) ∈ Ord ∪ {∞}

satisfying

N M(a, A) ≥ α + 1 ⇔ ∃B ⊇ fin A (N M(a, B) ≥ α ∧ ¬a ⌣∣ nm A B )

Example. N M(a, A) = 0 ⇔ a ∈ Acl eq (A).

(36)

Definition. (X , G) is nm-stable if every 1-orbit has ordinal rank, i.e.

there is no infinite sequence A 0 ⊆ A 1 ⊆ . . . ⊆ fin X and a ∈ X such that a is nm-dependent from A i +1 over A i .

Definition. If D is definable over A in X eq , the N M-rank of D is

N M(D) = sup{N M(d, A) ∣ d ∈ D}

(37)

Definition. (X , G) is nm-stable if every 1-orbit has ordinal rank, i.e.

there is no infinite sequence A 0 ⊆ A 1 ⊆ . . . ⊆ fin X and a ∈ X such that a is nm-dependent from A i +1 over A i .

Definition. If D is definable over A in X eq , the N M-rank of D is

N M(D) = sup{N M(d, A) ∣ d ∈ D}

(38)

Examples (Krupi´ nski)

▸ (S n , Homeo (S n )) has rank 1

▸ ((S 1 ) n , Homeo ((S 1 ) n )) has rank 1

▸ ([0, 1] N , Homeo ([0, 1] N )) has rank 1

▸ if (X , G) has rank 1, then (X n , G ) has rank n

(39)

Continua

Definitions.

▸ A continuum is a compact connected metric space; it is non-degenerate if it has more than one point

▸ A non-degenerate continuum X is decomposable if X = Y ∪ Z, for Y , Z some proper subcontinua of X . Otherwise it is indecomposable

▸ A non-degenerate continuum is hereditarily (in)decomposable if all

its subcontinua are (in)decomposable

(40)

Continua

Definitions.

▸ A continuum is a compact connected metric space; it is non-degenerate if it has more than one point

▸ A non-degenerate continuum X is decomposable if X = Y ∪ Z, for Y , Z some proper subcontinua of X . Otherwise it is indecomposable

▸ A non-degenerate continuum is hereditarily (in)decomposable if all

its subcontinua are (in)decomposable

(41)

Continua

Definitions.

▸ A continuum is a compact connected metric space; it is non-degenerate if it has more than one point

▸ A non-degenerate continuum X is decomposable if X = Y ∪ Z, for Y , Z some proper subcontinua of X . Otherwise it is indecomposable

▸ A non-degenerate continuum is hereditarily (in)decomposable if all

its subcontinua are (in)decomposable

(42)

The pseudo-arc

Definition. The pseudo-arc is the unique continuum that is hereditarily indecomposable and arc-like:

∀ε, ∃f ∶ P ↠ [0, 1] continuous , ∀y, diam(f −1 (y)) < ε

A construction of the pseudoarc:

Fix distinct point p, q ∈ R 2 .

Step 0 Draw a simple chain U 0 = {U 00 , . . . , U 0r

0

} from p to q of

connected open sets of diameter less than 1. Being a simple chain from p to q means:

▸ U i ∩ U j ⇔ ∣i − j∣ ≤ 1

▸ p ∈ U 0i ⇔ i = 0

▸ q ∈ U 0i ⇔ i = r 0

(43)

The pseudo-arc

Definition. The pseudo-arc is the unique continuum that is hereditarily indecomposable and arc-like:

∀ε, ∃f ∶ P ↠ [0, 1] continuous , ∀y, diam(f −1 (y)) < ε

A construction of the pseudoarc:

Fix distinct point p, q ∈ R 2 .

Step 0 Draw a simple chain U 0 = {U 00 , . . . , U 0r

0

} from p to q of

connected open sets of diameter less than 1. Being a simple chain from p to q means:

▸ U i ∩ U j ⇔ ∣i − j∣ ≤ 1

▸ p ∈ U 0i ⇔ i = 0

▸ q ∈ U 0i ⇔ i = r 0

(44)

The pseudo-arc

Definition. The pseudo-arc is the unique continuum that is hereditarily indecomposable and arc-like:

∀ε, ∃f ∶ P ↠ [0, 1] continuous , ∀y, diam(f −1 (y)) < ε

A construction of the pseudoarc:

Fix distinct point p, q ∈ R 2 .

Step 0 Draw a simple chain U 0 = {U 00 , . . . , U 0r

0

} from p to q of

connected open sets of diameter less than 1. Being a simple chain from p to q means:

▸ U i ∩ U j ⇔ ∣i − j∣ ≤ 1

▸ p ∈ U 0i ⇔ i = 0

▸ q ∈ U 0i ⇔ i = r 0

(45)

Step k+1 Draw a simple chain U k+1 = {U k+1,0 , . . . , U k+1,r

k+1

} from p to q of connected open sets of diameter less than k+2 1 such that

▸ the closure of each link of U k+1 is contained in some link of U k

▸ U k+1 is crooked in U k

This last condition means that for all i , j , m, n, if

m + 2 < n, U k+1,i ∩ U km ≠ ∅, U k+1,j ∩ U kn ≠ ∅ then there are s, t with i < s < t < j or i > t > l > j such that

U k+1,s ⊆ U k,n−1 and U k+1,t ⊆ U k,m+1

Final step P = ⋂ k∈N ⋃ U k is the pseudoarc.

(46)

Step k+1 Draw a simple chain U k+1 = {U k+1,0 , . . . , U k+1,r

k+1

} from p to q of connected open sets of diameter less than k+2 1 such that

▸ the closure of each link of U k+1 is contained in some link of U k

▸ U k+1 is crooked in U k

This last condition means that for all i , j , m, n, if

m + 2 < n, U k+1,i ∩ U km ≠ ∅, U k+1,j ∩ U kn ≠ ∅ then there are s, t with i < s < t < j or i > t > l > j such that

U k+1,s ⊆ U k,n−1 and U k+1,t ⊆ U k,m+1

Final step P = ⋂ k∈N ⋃ U k is the pseudoarc.

(47)

Step k+1 Draw a simple chain U k+1 = {U k+1,0 , . . . , U k+1,r

k+1

} from p to q of connected open sets of diameter less than k+2 1 such that

▸ the closure of each link of U k+1 is contained in some link of U k

▸ U k+1 is crooked in U k

This last condition means that for all i , j , m, n, if

m + 2 < n, U k+1,i ∩ U km ≠ ∅, U k+1,j ∩ U kn ≠ ∅

then there are s, t with i < s < t < j or i > t > l > j such that U k+1,s ⊆ U k,n−1 and U k+1,t ⊆ U k,m+1

Final step P = ⋂ k∈N ⋃ U k is the pseudoarc.

(48)

Step k+1 Draw a simple chain U k+1 = {U k+1,0 , . . . , U k+1,r

k+1

} from p to q of connected open sets of diameter less than k+2 1 such that

▸ the closure of each link of U k+1 is contained in some link of U k

▸ U k+1 is crooked in U k

This last condition means that for all i , j , m, n, if

m + 2 < n, U k+1,i ∩ U km ≠ ∅, U k+1,j ∩ U kn ≠ ∅ then there are s, t with i < s < t < j or i > t > l > j such that

U k+1,s ⊆ U k,n−1 and U k+1,t ⊆ U k,m+1

Final step P = ⋂ k∈N ⋃ U k is the pseudoarc.

(49)

Step k+1 Draw a simple chain U k+1 = {U k+1,0 , . . . , U k+1,r

k+1

} from p to q of connected open sets of diameter less than k+2 1 such that

▸ the closure of each link of U k+1 is contained in some link of U k

▸ U k+1 is crooked in U k

This last condition means that for all i , j , m, n, if

m + 2 < n, U k+1,i ∩ U km ≠ ∅, U k+1,j ∩ U kn ≠ ∅ then there are s, t with i < s < t < j or i > t > l > j such that

U k+1,s ⊆ U k,n−1 and U k+1,t ⊆ U k,m+1

Final step P = ⋂ k∈N ⋃ U k is the pseudoarc.

(50)

The pseudo-arc is a quite complicated continuum. Nevertheless it is the generic continuum: the class of pseudo-arcs is dense G δ in the space of all continua.

Theorem. (Krupi´ nski) Let P be the pseudo-arc. Then (P, Homeo(P)) is a small, not nm-stable, Polish structure.

In particular, the N M-rank of P is ∞.

Moreover P is an example of a small Polish structure not admitting

o-independent extensions.

(51)

The pseudo-arc is a quite complicated continuum. Nevertheless it is the generic continuum: the class of pseudo-arcs is dense G δ in the space of all continua.

Theorem. (Krupi´ nski) Let P be the pseudo-arc. Then (P, Homeo(P)) is a small, not nm-stable, Polish structure.

In particular, the N M-rank of P is ∞.

Moreover P is an example of a small Polish structure not admitting

o-independent extensions.

(52)

The pseudo-arc is a quite complicated continuum. Nevertheless it is the generic continuum: the class of pseudo-arcs is dense G δ in the space of all continua.

Theorem. (Krupi´ nski) Let P be the pseudo-arc. Then (P, Homeo(P)) is a small, not nm-stable, Polish structure.

In particular, the N M-rank of P is ∞.

Moreover P is an example of a small Polish structure not admitting

o-independent extensions.

(53)

Dendrites

Among simplest continua are dendrites.

A dendrite is a locally connected continuum that does not contain simple closed curves.

Definition. Given a point x in a continuum X , its order ord (x, X ) is the smallest cardinal β such that x has a basis of open neighbourhoods whose boundaries have cardinality ≤ β.

All points of a dendrite have order ≤ ℵ 0 . Points of order 1 are called end

points; points of order ≥ 3 are branching points.

(54)

Dendrites

Among simplest continua are dendrites.

A dendrite is a locally connected continuum that does not contain simple closed curves.

Definition. Given a point x in a continuum X , its order ord (x, X ) is the smallest cardinal β such that x has a basis of open neighbourhoods whose boundaries have cardinality ≤ β.

All points of a dendrite have order ≤ ℵ 0 . Points of order 1 are called end

points; points of order ≥ 3 are branching points.

(55)

Dendrites

Among simplest continua are dendrites.

A dendrite is a locally connected continuum that does not contain simple closed curves.

Definition. Given a point x in a continuum X , its order ord (x, X ) is the smallest cardinal β such that x has a basis of open neighbourhoods whose boundaries have cardinality ≤ β.

All points of a dendrite have order ≤ ℵ 0 . Points of order 1 are called end

points; points of order ≥ 3 are branching points.

(56)

The following property might help to visualise a dendrite:

If X is a non-degenerate dendrite, then X = ⋃

i ∈N

A i ∪ E(X ) where:

▸ each A i is an arc, with end points p i , q i

▸ A i +1 ∩ ⋃ i j =0 A j = {p i +1 }

▸ diam (A i ) → 0

▸ E (X ) is the set of end points of X

(57)

The goal is to study Polish structures of the form (D, Homeo(D)) where D is a dendrite.

Remark. Not all dendrites are small Polish structures. Let D ⊆ R 2 be obtained by starting with [0, 1] × {0} as follows:

▸ enumerate {q n } n∈N = (]0, 1[∩Q) × {0}

▸ at step n add n arcs of diameter ≤ 2 1

n

intersecting each other and the already achieved construction only in q n

Then all point of ]0, 1[×{0} are in distinct orbits.

(58)

The goal is to study Polish structures of the form (D, Homeo(D)) where D is a dendrite.

Remark. Not all dendrites are small Polish structures. Let D ⊆ R 2 be obtained by starting with [0, 1] × {0} as follows:

▸ enumerate {q n } n∈N = (]0, 1[∩Q) × {0}

▸ at step n add n arcs of diameter ≤ 2 1

n

intersecting each other and the already achieved construction only in q n

Then all point of ]0, 1[×{0} are in distinct orbits.

(59)

The goal is to study Polish structures of the form (D, Homeo(D)) where D is a dendrite.

Remark. Not all dendrites are small Polish structures. Let D ⊆ R 2 be obtained by starting with [0, 1] × {0} as follows:

▸ enumerate {q n } n∈N = (]0, 1[∩Q) × {0}

▸ at step n add n arcs of diameter ≤ 2 1

n

intersecting each other and the already achieved construction only in q n

Then all point of ]0, 1[×{0} are in distinct orbits.

(60)

The goal is to study Polish structures of the form (D, Homeo(D)) where D is a dendrite.

Remark. Not all dendrites are small Polish structures. Let D ⊆ R 2 be obtained by starting with [0, 1] × {0} as follows:

▸ enumerate {q n } n∈N = (]0, 1[∩Q) × {0}

▸ at step n add n arcs of diameter ≤ 2 1

n

intersecting each other and the already achieved construction only in q n

Then all point of ]0, 1[×{0} are in distinct orbits.

(61)

Wa˙zewski’s universal dendrites

Let ∅ ≠ J ⊆ {3, 4 . . . , ω}.

There is a unique dendrite D J such that

▸ each branching point of D J has order in J

▸ each subarc of D J contains points of any order in J

Universality property

D J is universal for the class of dendrites whose branching points have

order in J: any such dendrite embeds in D J .

(62)

Wa˙zewski’s universal dendrites

Let ∅ ≠ J ⊆ {3, 4 . . . , ω}.

There is a unique dendrite D J such that

▸ each branching point of D J has order in J

▸ each subarc of D J contains points of any order in J Universality property

D J is universal for the class of dendrites whose branching points have

order in J: any such dendrite embeds in D J .

(63)

Theorem. Each (D J , Homeo (D J )) is a small Polish structure of N M-rank 1

Conjectures.

▸ Each dendrite admits nm-independent extensions

▸ If D is a dendrite and (D, Homeo(D)) is small, then N M(D) = 1

(64)

Theorem. Each (D J , Homeo (D J )) is a small Polish structure of N M-rank 1

Conjectures.

▸ Each dendrite admits nm-independent extensions

▸ If D is a dendrite and (D, Homeo(D)) is small, then N M(D) = 1

(65)

Some questions.

▸ Characterise dendrites D such that (D, Homeo(D)) is small.

▸ Find examples of continua C with 1 < N M(C) < ∞.

▸ The N M-gap conjecture.

(66)

Some questions.

▸ Characterise dendrites D such that (D, Homeo(D)) is small.

▸ Find examples of continua C with 1 < N M(C) < ∞.

▸ The N M-gap conjecture.

(67)

Some questions.

▸ Characterise dendrites D such that (D, Homeo(D)) is small.

▸ Find examples of continua C with 1 < N M(C) < ∞.

▸ The N M-gap conjecture.

(68)

An example of a small Polish structure (X , G) with N M(X ) = ω can be obtained as a disjoint sum of small Polish structures of increasing natural rank.

E.g., take (Y , G) of rank 1 an let X = ⋃ n≥1 X n .

However, in this example the is no single orbit over finite sets with rank

≥ ω (and ≠ ∞).

The N M-gap conjecture. Let (X , G) be a small Polish structure. Then, for any orbit o of a finite set A ⊆ X , one has

N M(o) ∈ ω ∪ {∞}.

This conjecture is open in the class of small profinite structures; it has

been proved for small m-stable profinite groups. In this wider context it

might be easier to find a counterexample.

(69)

An example of a small Polish structure (X , G) with N M(X ) = ω can be obtained as a disjoint sum of small Polish structures of increasing natural rank.

E.g., take (Y , G) of rank 1 an let X = ⋃ n≥1 X n .

However, in this example the is no single orbit over finite sets with rank

≥ ω (and ≠ ∞).

The N M-gap conjecture. Let (X , G) be a small Polish structure. Then, for any orbit o of a finite set A ⊆ X , one has

N M(o) ∈ ω ∪ {∞}.

This conjecture is open in the class of small profinite structures; it has

been proved for small m-stable profinite groups. In this wider context it

might be easier to find a counterexample.

(70)

An example of a small Polish structure (X , G) with N M(X ) = ω can be obtained as a disjoint sum of small Polish structures of increasing natural rank.

E.g., take (Y , G) of rank 1 an let X = ⋃ n≥1 X n .

However, in this example the is no single orbit over finite sets with rank

≥ ω (and ≠ ∞).

The N M-gap conjecture. Let (X , G) be a small Polish structure.

Then, for any orbit o of a finite set A ⊆ X , one has N M(o) ∈ ω ∪ {∞}.

This conjecture is open in the class of small profinite structures; it has

been proved for small m-stable profinite groups. In this wider context it

might be easier to find a counterexample.

(71)

An example of a small Polish structure (X , G) with N M(X ) = ω can be obtained as a disjoint sum of small Polish structures of increasing natural rank.

E.g., take (Y , G) of rank 1 an let X = ⋃ n≥1 X n .

However, in this example the is no single orbit over finite sets with rank

≥ ω (and ≠ ∞).

The N M-gap conjecture. Let (X , G) be a small Polish structure.

Then, for any orbit o of a finite set A ⊆ X , one has N M(o) ∈ ω ∪ {∞}.

This conjecture is open in the class of small profinite structures; it has

been proved for small m-stable profinite groups. In this wider context it

might be easier to find a counterexample.

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

7KHUHVHDUFK FRRUGLQDWRUSURI)'0RFFLD LQZKLFK,SDUWLFLSDWHGIRUWKHXUEDQGHVLJQDQGSROLFLHVVXSSRUW FRYHUHG WKH ZDWHUIURQW RI &amp;DVWHOODPPDUH ZKLFK IRU

is shown to be decidable by using a technique that also proves, as a by-product, a reflection result on the hereditarily finite sets for that class of formulae.. Notice that this is

Operators like ∂/ ⊗ ∆ + that involve Betti numbers will be rigid, meaning that the indices are sums of trivial modules..

Our results provide a statistical justi…cation for this approach: speci…cally, we proved that it guarantees (i) a convergence rate faster than the T rate of standard OLS estimators

Con alcuni soggetti la collaborazione è stata immediata, in particolare con le realtà che già erano in contatto con l’Osservatorio CORES, grazie ad esempio alla Rete di

(Marcone, Rosendal) The relation of continuous embeddability on dendrites is a universal analytic

Mimicking some of the Wadge’s constructions on the Baire space, there are candidate operations performing task 1... .). Mimicking some of the Wadge’s constructions on the Baire

I Effective descriptive set theory was created later by introducing into the classical theory the new and powerful tools developed from recursion theory.... Descriptive set