• Non ci sono risultati.

Invariant descriptive set theory

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Invariant descriptive set theory"

Copied!
95
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

Invariant descriptive set theory

(2)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

Invariant descriptive set theory is the study of the complexity of equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces.

Motivation. In mathematics one often looks for complete invariants to assign to some notion of equivalence:

I Vector spaces on some fixed field are isomorphic iff they have the same dimension

I Compact orientable surfaces are homeomorphic iff they have the same genus

I Complex square matrices are similar iff they have the same Jordan normal form

I (Ornstein) Bernoulli shifts are isomorphic if they have the same entropy

I . . .

(3)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

Invariant descriptive set theory is the study of the complexity of equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces.

Motivation. In mathematics one often looks for complete invariants to assign to some notion of equivalence:

I Vector spaces on some fixed field are isomorphic iff they have the same dimension

I Compact orientable surfaces are homeomorphic iff they have the same genus

I Complex square matrices are similar iff they have the same Jordan normal form

I (Ornstein) Bernoulli shifts are isomorphic if they have the same entropy

I . . .

(4)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

Invariant descriptive set theory is the study of the complexity of equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces.

Motivation. In mathematics one often looks for complete invariants to assign to some notion of equivalence:

I Vector spaces on some fixed field are isomorphic iff they have the same dimension

I Compact orientable surfaces are homeomorphic iff they have the same genus

I Complex square matrices are similar iff they have the same Jordan normal form

I (Ornstein) Bernoulli shifts are isomorphic if they have the same entropy

I . . .

(5)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

Invariant descriptive set theory is the study of the complexity of equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces.

Motivation. In mathematics one often looks for complete invariants to assign to some notion of equivalence:

I Vector spaces on some fixed field are isomorphic iff they have the same dimension

I Compact orientable surfaces are homeomorphic iff they have the same genus

I Complex square matrices are similar iff they have the same Jordan normal form

I (Ornstein) Bernoulli shifts are isomorphic if they have the same entropy

I . . .

(6)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

Invariant descriptive set theory is the study of the complexity of equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces.

Motivation. In mathematics one often looks for complete invariants to assign to some notion of equivalence:

I Vector spaces on some fixed field are isomorphic iff they have the same dimension

I Compact orientable surfaces are homeomorphic iff they have the same genus

I Complex square matrices are similar iff they have the same Jordan normal form

I (Ornstein) Bernoulli shifts are isomorphic if they have the same entropy

I . . .

(7)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

Invariant descriptive set theory is the study of the complexity of equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces.

Motivation. In mathematics one often looks for complete invariants to assign to some notion of equivalence:

I Vector spaces on some fixed field are isomorphic iff they have the same dimension

I Compact orientable surfaces are homeomorphic iff they have the same genus

I Complex square matrices are similar iff they have the same Jordan normal form

I (Ornstein) Bernoulli shifts are isomorphic if they have the same entropy

I . . .

(8)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

Invariant descriptive set theory is the study of the complexity of equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces.

Motivation. In mathematics one often looks for complete invariants to assign to some notion of equivalence:

I Vector spaces on some fixed field are isomorphic iff they have the same dimension

I Compact orientable surfaces are homeomorphic iff they have the same genus

I Complex square matrices are similar iff they have the same Jordan normal form

I (Ornstein) Bernoulli shifts are isomorphic if they have the same entropy

I . . .

(9)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

I (Baer) To each countable torsion free Abelian group G of rank 1 it is possible to assign a sequence hG of natural numbers s.t. G ∼ G0 iff hG, hG0 are eventually equal

I Commutative AF -algebras are isomorphic iff their dimension groups are isomorphic

I . . .

In order for these assignment to be of some use, they should be sufficiently effective.

The right notion of effectiveness turns out to be that of a Borel function, provided the collections of objects to be classified form a standard Borel space — which is often the case.

(10)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

I (Baer) To each countable torsion free Abelian group G of rank 1 it is possible to assign a sequence hG of natural numbers s.t. G ∼ G0 iff hG, hG0 are eventually equal

I Commutative AF -algebras are isomorphic iff their dimension groups are isomorphic

I . . .

In order for these assignment to be of some use, they should be sufficiently effective.

The right notion of effectiveness turns out to be that of a Borel function, provided the collections of objects to be classified form a standard Borel space — which is often the case.

(11)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

I (Baer) To each countable torsion free Abelian group G of rank 1 it is possible to assign a sequence hG of natural numbers s.t. G ∼ G0 iff hG, hG0 are eventually equal

I Commutative AF -algebras are isomorphic iff their dimension groups are isomorphic

I . . .

In order for these assignment to be of some use, they should be sufficiently effective.

The right notion of effectiveness turns out to be that of a Borel function, provided the collections of objects to be classified form a standard Borel space — which is often the case.

(12)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

I (Baer) To each countable torsion free Abelian group G of rank 1 it is possible to assign a sequence hG of natural numbers s.t. G ∼ G0 iff hG, hG0 are eventually equal

I Commutative AF -algebras are isomorphic iff their dimension groups are isomorphic

I . . .

In order for these assignment to be of some use, they should be sufficiently effective.

The right notion of effectiveness turns out to be that of a Borel function,

provided the collections of objects to be classified form a standard Borel space — which is often the case.

(13)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

I (Baer) To each countable torsion free Abelian group G of rank 1 it is possible to assign a sequence hG of natural numbers s.t. G ∼ G0 iff hG, hG0 are eventually equal

I Commutative AF -algebras are isomorphic iff their dimension groups are isomorphic

I . . .

In order for these assignment to be of some use, they should be sufficiently effective.

The right notion of effectiveness turns out to be that of a Borel function, provided the collections of objects to be classified form a standard Borel space —

which is often the case.

(14)

Invariant descriptive set theory: an introduction

I (Baer) To each countable torsion free Abelian group G of rank 1 it is possible to assign a sequence hG of natural numbers s.t. G ∼ G0 iff hG, hG0 are eventually equal

I Commutative AF -algebras are isomorphic iff their dimension groups are isomorphic

I . . .

In order for these assignment to be of some use, they should be sufficiently effective.

The right notion of effectiveness turns out to be that of a Borel function, provided the collections of objects to be classified form a standard Borel space — which is often the case.

(15)

Borel reducibility

Definition

Let E , F be equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , resp. Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted

E ≤B F , iff there is f : X → Y Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0⇔ f (x)Ff (x0))

When E ≤B F , any classification of objects in Y up to F -equivalence can be translated to a classification of objects of X up to E -equivalence, by applying function f . In this sense, the complexity of E is less than or equal to the complexity of F .

If E ≤B F ≤B E , one writes E ∼B F : the equivalence relations E , F are Borel bireducible.

(16)

Borel reducibility

Definition

Let E , F be equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , resp.

Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted E ≤B F , iff there is f : X → Y Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0⇔ f (x)Ff (x0))

When E ≤B F , any classification of objects in Y up to F -equivalence can be translated to a classification of objects of X up to E -equivalence, by applying function f . In this sense, the complexity of E is less than or equal to the complexity of F .

If E ≤B F ≤B E , one writes E ∼B F : the equivalence relations E , F are Borel bireducible.

(17)

Borel reducibility

Definition

Let E , F be equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , resp.

Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted E ≤B F ,

iff there is f : X → Y Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0⇔ f (x)Ff (x0))

When E ≤B F , any classification of objects in Y up to F -equivalence can be translated to a classification of objects of X up to E -equivalence, by applying function f . In this sense, the complexity of E is less than or equal to the complexity of F .

If E ≤B F ≤B E , one writes E ∼B F : the equivalence relations E , F are Borel bireducible.

(18)

Borel reducibility

Definition

Let E , F be equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , resp.

Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted E ≤B F , iff there is f : X → Y Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0⇔ f (x)Ff (x0))

When E ≤B F , any classification of objects in Y up to F -equivalence can be translated to a classification of objects of X up to E -equivalence, by applying function f .

In this sense, the complexity of E is less than or equal to the complexity of F .

If E ≤B F ≤B E , one writes E ∼B F : the equivalence relations E , F are Borel bireducible.

(19)

Borel reducibility

Definition

Let E , F be equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , resp.

Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted E ≤B F , iff there is f : X → Y Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0⇔ f (x)Ff (x0))

When E ≤B F , any classification of objects in Y up to F -equivalence can be translated to a classification of objects of X up to E -equivalence, by applying function f . In this sense, the complexity of E is less than or equal to the complexity of F .

If E ≤B F ≤B E , one writes E ∼B F : the equivalence relations E , F are Borel bireducible.

(20)

Borel reducibility

Definition

Let E , F be equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , resp.

Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted E ≤B F , iff there is f : X → Y Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0⇔ f (x)Ff (x0))

When E ≤B F , any classification of objects in Y up to F -equivalence can be translated to a classification of objects of X up to E -equivalence, by applying function f . In this sense, the complexity of E is less than or equal to the complexity of F .

If E ≤B F ≤B E , one writes E ∼B F : the equivalence relations E , F are Borel bireducible.

(21)

Smooth equivalence relations

Among the simplest equivalence relations are those whose classes can be characterised by a single real number:

Definition

An equivalence relation E on a standard Borel X is smooth if E ≤B=, i.e., there exists f : X → R Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0 ⇔ f (x) = f (x0))

Fact

Given two uncountable standard Borel spaces Y , Z there is always a Borel isomorphism g : Y → Z .

(22)

Smooth equivalence relations

Among the simplest equivalence relations are those whose classes can be characterised by a single real number:

Definition

An equivalence relation E on a standard Borel X is smooth if E ≤B=, i.e., there exists f : X → R Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0 ⇔ f (x) = f (x0))

Fact

Given two uncountable standard Borel spaces Y , Z there is always a Borel isomorphism g : Y → Z .

(23)

Smooth equivalence relations

Among the simplest equivalence relations are those whose classes can be characterised by a single real number:

Definition

An equivalence relation E on a standard Borel X is smooth if E ≤B=,

i.e., there exists f : X → R Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0 ⇔ f (x) = f (x0))

Fact

Given two uncountable standard Borel spaces Y , Z there is always a Borel isomorphism g : Y → Z .

(24)

Smooth equivalence relations

Among the simplest equivalence relations are those whose classes can be characterised by a single real number:

Definition

An equivalence relation E on a standard Borel X is smooth if E ≤B=, i.e., there exists f : X → R Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0⇔ f (x) = f (x0))

Fact

Given two uncountable standard Borel spaces Y , Z there is always a Borel isomorphism g : Y → Z .

(25)

Smooth equivalence relations

Among the simplest equivalence relations are those whose classes can be characterised by a single real number:

Definition

An equivalence relation E on a standard Borel X is smooth if E ≤B=, i.e., there exists f : X → R Borel s.t.

∀x, x0∈ X (xEx0⇔ f (x) = f (x0))

Fact

Given two uncountable standard Borel spaces Y , Z there is always a Borel isomorphism g : Y → Z .

(26)

Smooth equivalence relations

So an equivalence relation is smooth if Borel reduces to equality on some uncountable standard Borel spaces

Using this, the following equivalence relations are smooth:

I Homeomorphism on compact orientable surfaces

I Similarity on complex square matrices

I Isomorphism on Bernoulli shifts

I (Gromov) Isometry on compact metric spaces

I . . .

(27)

Smooth equivalence relations

So an equivalence relation is smooth if Borel reduces to equality on some uncountable standard Borel spaces

Using this, the following equivalence relations are smooth:

I Homeomorphism on compact orientable surfaces

I Similarity on complex square matrices

I Isomorphism on Bernoulli shifts

I (Gromov) Isometry on compact metric spaces

I . . .

(28)

Non-smooth equivalence relations

Not all equivalence relations are smooth:

Examples

I Vitali equivalence. On R let xEVy ⇔ x − y ∈ Q.

I Eventual equality on NN. Let xE0y ⇔ ∀n x (n) = y (n).

I Isomorphism 'TFA1 for torsion free Abelian groups of rank 1. It turns out that =R<B EV B E0B'TFA1.

(29)

Non-smooth equivalence relations

Not all equivalence relations are smooth:

Examples

I Vitali equivalence.

On R let xEVy ⇔ x − y ∈ Q.

I Eventual equality on NN. Let xE0y ⇔ ∀n x (n) = y (n).

I Isomorphism 'TFA1 for torsion free Abelian groups of rank 1. It turns out that =R<B EV B E0B'TFA1.

(30)

Non-smooth equivalence relations

Not all equivalence relations are smooth:

Examples

I Vitali equivalence. On R let xEVy ⇔ x − y ∈ Q.

I Eventual equality on NN. Let xE0y ⇔ ∀n x (n) = y (n).

I Isomorphism 'TFA1 for torsion free Abelian groups of rank 1. It turns out that =R<B EV B E0B'TFA1.

(31)

Non-smooth equivalence relations

Not all equivalence relations are smooth:

Examples

I Vitali equivalence. On R let xEVy ⇔ x − y ∈ Q.

I Eventual equality on NN.

Let xE0y ⇔ ∀n x (n) = y (n).

I Isomorphism 'TFA1 for torsion free Abelian groups of rank 1. It turns out that =R<B EV B E0B'TFA1.

(32)

Non-smooth equivalence relations

Not all equivalence relations are smooth:

Examples

I Vitali equivalence. On R let xEVy ⇔ x − y ∈ Q.

I Eventual equality on NN. Let xE0y ⇔ ∀n x (n) = y (n).

I Isomorphism 'TFA1 for torsion free Abelian groups of rank 1.

It turns out that =R<B EV B E0B'TFA1.

(33)

Non-smooth equivalence relations

Not all equivalence relations are smooth:

Examples

I Vitali equivalence. On R let xEVy ⇔ x − y ∈ Q.

I Eventual equality on NN. Let xE0y ⇔ ∀n x (n) = y (n).

I Isomorphism 'TFA1 for torsion free Abelian groups of rank 1.

It turns out that =R<B EV B E0B'TFA1.

(34)

Spaces of countable structures

Let

L = {Ri, fj, ck | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K }

be a countable first-order language, where ni, mj are the arities of Ri, fj, resp. A countable structure A — say with universe N — is defined by fixing interpretations

I RiA⊆ Nni, i.e. RiA∈ 2Nni, for each i ∈ I

I fjA: Nmj → N, i.e. fjA∈ NNmj, for each j ∈ J

I ckA∈ N, for each k ∈ K So

A ∈ (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK and

XL= (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

is the Polish space of countable L-structures (with universe N)

(35)

Spaces of countable structures

Let

L = {Ri, fj, ck | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K }

be a countable first-order language, where ni, mj are the arities of Ri, fj, resp.

A countable structure A — say with universe N — is defined by fixing interpretations

I RiA⊆ Nni, i.e. RiA∈ 2Nni, for each i ∈ I

I fjA: Nmj → N, i.e. fjA∈ NNmj, for each j ∈ J

I ckA∈ N, for each k ∈ K So

A ∈ (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK and

XL= (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

is the Polish space of countable L-structures (with universe N)

(36)

Spaces of countable structures

Let

L = {Ri, fj, ck | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K }

be a countable first-order language, where ni, mj are the arities of Ri, fj, resp. A countable structure A — say with universe N — is defined by fixing interpretations

I RiA⊆ Nni, i.e. RiA∈ 2Nni, for each i ∈ I

I fjA: Nmj → N, i.e. fjA∈ NNmj, for each j ∈ J

I ckA∈ N, for each k ∈ K So

A ∈ (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK and

XL= (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

is the Polish space of countable L-structures (with universe N)

(37)

Spaces of countable structures

Let

L = {Ri, fj, ck | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K }

be a countable first-order language, where ni, mj are the arities of Ri, fj, resp. A countable structure A — say with universe N — is defined by fixing interpretations

I RiA⊆ Nni,

i.e. RiA∈ 2Nni, for each i ∈ I

I fjA: Nmj → N, i.e. fjA∈ NNmj, for each j ∈ J

I ckA∈ N, for each k ∈ K So

A ∈ (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK and

XL= (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

is the Polish space of countable L-structures (with universe N)

(38)

Spaces of countable structures

Let

L = {Ri, fj, ck | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K }

be a countable first-order language, where ni, mj are the arities of Ri, fj, resp. A countable structure A — say with universe N — is defined by fixing interpretations

I RiA⊆ Nni, i.e. RiA∈ 2Nni, for each i ∈ I

I fjA: Nmj → N,

i.e. fjA∈ NNmj, for each j ∈ J

I ckA∈ N, for each k ∈ K So

A ∈ (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK and

XL= (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

is the Polish space of countable L-structures (with universe N)

(39)

Spaces of countable structures

Let

L = {Ri, fj, ck | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K }

be a countable first-order language, where ni, mj are the arities of Ri, fj, resp. A countable structure A — say with universe N — is defined by fixing interpretations

I RiA⊆ Nni, i.e. RiA∈ 2Nni, for each i ∈ I

I fjA: Nmj → N, i.e. fjA∈ NNmj, for each j ∈ J

I ckA∈ N, for each k ∈ K

So

A ∈ (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK and

XL= (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

is the Polish space of countable L-structures (with universe N)

(40)

Spaces of countable structures

Let

L = {Ri, fj, ck | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K }

be a countable first-order language, where ni, mj are the arities of Ri, fj, resp. A countable structure A — say with universe N — is defined by fixing interpretations

I RiA⊆ Nni, i.e. RiA∈ 2Nni, for each i ∈ I

I fjA: Nmj → N, i.e. fjA∈ NNmj, for each j ∈ J

I ckA∈ N, for each k ∈ K So

A ∈ (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

and

XL= (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

is the Polish space of countable L-structures (with universe N)

(41)

Spaces of countable structures

Let

L = {Ri, fj, ck | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K }

be a countable first-order language, where ni, mj are the arities of Ri, fj, resp. A countable structure A — say with universe N — is defined by fixing interpretations

I RiA⊆ Nni, i.e. RiA∈ 2Nni, for each i ∈ I

I fjA: Nmj → N, i.e. fjA∈ NNmj, for each j ∈ J

I ckA∈ N, for each k ∈ K So

A ∈ (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK and

XL= (Y

i ∈I

2Nni) × (Y

j ∈J

NNmj) × NK

is the Polish space of countable L-structures (with universe N)

(42)

The logic action

To simplify notation, from now on I will assume that L is relational, i.e., XL=Y

i ∈I

2Nni

Elements of XL will be usually denoted by letters like x , y , . . ..

Let S= Sym(N) be the group of permutations of N. This is a Gδ subset of NN: for every g ∈ NN, one has g ∈ S iff

1. g is surjective: ∀m ∃n g (n) = m

2. g is injective: ∀n, m (n 6= m ⇒ g (n) 6= g (m))

So Sis a Polish space. Moreover, the operations of composition (g , h) 7→ gh and inversion g 7→ g−1 are continuous in S, so it is a Polish group.

(43)

The logic action

To simplify notation, from now on I will assume that L is relational, i.e., XL=Y

i ∈I

2Nni

Elements of XL will be usually denoted by letters like x , y , . . ..

Let S= Sym(N) be the group of permutations of N.

This is a Gδ

subset of NN: for every g ∈ NN, one has g ∈ S iff 1. g is surjective: ∀m ∃n g (n) = m

2. g is injective: ∀n, m (n 6= m ⇒ g (n) 6= g (m))

So Sis a Polish space. Moreover, the operations of composition (g , h) 7→ gh and inversion g 7→ g−1 are continuous in S, so it is a Polish group.

(44)

The logic action

To simplify notation, from now on I will assume that L is relational, i.e., XL=Y

i ∈I

2Nni

Elements of XL will be usually denoted by letters like x , y , . . ..

Let S= Sym(N) be the group of permutations of N. This is a Gδ subset of NN:

for every g ∈ NN, one has g ∈ S iff 1. g is surjective: ∀m ∃n g (n) = m

2. g is injective: ∀n, m (n 6= m ⇒ g (n) 6= g (m))

So Sis a Polish space. Moreover, the operations of composition (g , h) 7→ gh and inversion g 7→ g−1 are continuous in S, so it is a Polish group.

(45)

The logic action

To simplify notation, from now on I will assume that L is relational, i.e., XL=Y

i ∈I

2Nni

Elements of XL will be usually denoted by letters like x , y , . . ..

Let S= Sym(N) be the group of permutations of N. This is a Gδ subset of NN: for every g ∈ NN, one has g ∈ S iff

1. g is surjective: ∀m ∃n g (n) = m

2. g is injective: ∀n, m (n 6= m ⇒ g (n) 6= g (m))

So Sis a Polish space. Moreover, the operations of composition (g , h) 7→ gh and inversion g 7→ g−1 are continuous in S, so it is a Polish group.

(46)

The logic action

To simplify notation, from now on I will assume that L is relational, i.e., XL=Y

i ∈I

2Nni

Elements of XL will be usually denoted by letters like x , y , . . ..

Let S= Sym(N) be the group of permutations of N. This is a Gδ subset of NN: for every g ∈ NN, one has g ∈ S iff

1. g is surjective: ∀m ∃n g (n) = m

2. g is injective: ∀n, m (n 6= m ⇒ g (n) 6= g (m))

So Sis a Polish space. Moreover, the operations of composition (g , h) 7→ gh and inversion g 7→ g−1 are continuous in S, so it is a Polish group.

(47)

The logic action

To simplify notation, from now on I will assume that L is relational, i.e., XL=Y

i ∈I

2Nni

Elements of XL will be usually denoted by letters like x , y , . . ..

Let S= Sym(N) be the group of permutations of N. This is a Gδ subset of NN: for every g ∈ NN, one has g ∈ S iff

1. g is surjective: ∀m ∃n g (n) = m

2. g is injective: ∀n, m (n 6= m ⇒ g (n) 6= g (m)) So Sis a Polish space.

Moreover, the operations of composition (g , h) 7→ gh and inversion g 7→ g−1 are continuous in S, so it is a Polish group.

(48)

The logic action

To simplify notation, from now on I will assume that L is relational, i.e., XL=Y

i ∈I

2Nni

Elements of XL will be usually denoted by letters like x , y , . . ..

Let S= Sym(N) be the group of permutations of N. This is a Gδ subset of NN: for every g ∈ NN, one has g ∈ S iff

1. g is surjective: ∀m ∃n g (n) = m

2. g is injective: ∀n, m (n 6= m ⇒ g (n) 6= g (m))

So Sis a Polish space. Moreover, the operations of composition (g , h) 7→ gh and inversion g 7→ g−1 are continuous in S,

so it is a Polish group.

(49)

The logic action

To simplify notation, from now on I will assume that L is relational, i.e., XL=Y

i ∈I

2Nni

Elements of XL will be usually denoted by letters like x , y , . . ..

Let S= Sym(N) be the group of permutations of N. This is a Gδ subset of NN: for every g ∈ NN, one has g ∈ S iff

1. g is surjective: ∀m ∃n g (n) = m

2. g is injective: ∀n, m (n 6= m ⇒ g (n) 6= g (m))

So Sis a Polish space. Moreover, the operations of composition (g , h) 7→ gh and inversion g 7→ g−1 are continuous in S, so it is a Polish group.

(50)

The logic action

The action of S on N induces an action of Son XL, the logic action:

gx = y ⇔ ∀i yi(h1, . . . , hn) = xi(g−1(h1), . . . , g−1(hn)) i.e., gx = y iff g : N → N is an isomorphism between the L-structures x , y . The orbit equivalence relation is isomorphism:

x ' y ⇔ ∃g ∈ S gx = y .

Definition

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic if it is the Borel image of a Borel subset of a standard Borel space:

A ∈ Σ11(X ) ⇔ ∃f : Y → X Borel ∃B ∈ B(Y ) f (B) = A So the isomorphism relation ' on XL is analytic, as a subset of XL2(but in general not Borel).

(51)

The logic action

The action of S on N induces an action of Son XL, the logic action:

gx = y ⇔ ∀i yi(h1, . . . , hn) = xi(g−1(h1), . . . , g−1(hn))

i.e., gx = y iff g : N → N is an isomorphism between the L-structures x , y . The orbit equivalence relation is isomorphism:

x ' y ⇔ ∃g ∈ S gx = y .

Definition

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic if it is the Borel image of a Borel subset of a standard Borel space:

A ∈ Σ11(X ) ⇔ ∃f : Y → X Borel ∃B ∈ B(Y ) f (B) = A So the isomorphism relation ' on XL is analytic, as a subset of XL2(but in general not Borel).

(52)

The logic action

The action of S on N induces an action of Son XL, the logic action:

gx = y ⇔ ∀i yi(h1, . . . , hn) = xi(g−1(h1), . . . , g−1(hn)) i.e., gx = y iff g : N → N is an isomorphism between the L-structures x , y .

The orbit equivalence relation is isomorphism: x ' y ⇔ ∃g ∈ S gx = y .

Definition

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic if it is the Borel image of a Borel subset of a standard Borel space:

A ∈ Σ11(X ) ⇔ ∃f : Y → X Borel ∃B ∈ B(Y ) f (B) = A So the isomorphism relation ' on XL is analytic, as a subset of XL2(but in general not Borel).

(53)

The logic action

The action of S on N induces an action of Son XL, the logic action:

gx = y ⇔ ∀i yi(h1, . . . , hn) = xi(g−1(h1), . . . , g−1(hn)) i.e., gx = y iff g : N → N is an isomorphism between the L-structures x , y . The orbit equivalence relation is isomorphism:

x ' y ⇔ ∃g ∈ S gx = y .

Definition

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic if it is the Borel image of a Borel subset of a standard Borel space:

A ∈ Σ11(X ) ⇔ ∃f : Y → X Borel ∃B ∈ B(Y ) f (B) = A So the isomorphism relation ' on XL is analytic, as a subset of XL2(but in general not Borel).

(54)

The logic action

The action of S on N induces an action of Son XL, the logic action:

gx = y ⇔ ∀i yi(h1, . . . , hn) = xi(g−1(h1), . . . , g−1(hn)) i.e., gx = y iff g : N → N is an isomorphism between the L-structures x , y . The orbit equivalence relation is isomorphism:

x ' y ⇔ ∃g ∈ S gx = y .

Definition

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic if it is the Borel image of a Borel subset of a standard Borel space:

A ∈ Σ11(X ) ⇔ ∃f : Y → X Borel ∃B ∈ B(Y ) f (B) = A So the isomorphism relation ' on XL is analytic, as a subset of XL2(but in general not Borel).

(55)

The logic action

The action of S on N induces an action of Son XL, the logic action:

gx = y ⇔ ∀i yi(h1, . . . , hn) = xi(g−1(h1), . . . , g−1(hn)) i.e., gx = y iff g : N → N is an isomorphism between the L-structures x , y . The orbit equivalence relation is isomorphism:

x ' y ⇔ ∃g ∈ S gx = y .

Definition

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic if it is the Borel image of a Borel subset of a standard Borel space:

A ∈ Σ11(X ) ⇔ ∃f : Y → X Borel ∃B ∈ B(Y ) f (B) = A

So the isomorphism relation ' on XL is analytic, as a subset of XL2(but in general not Borel).

(56)

The logic action

The action of S on N induces an action of Son XL, the logic action:

gx = y ⇔ ∀i yi(h1, . . . , hn) = xi(g−1(h1), . . . , g−1(hn)) i.e., gx = y iff g : N → N is an isomorphism between the L-structures x , y . The orbit equivalence relation is isomorphism:

x ' y ⇔ ∃g ∈ S gx = y .

Definition

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic if it is the Borel image of a Borel subset of a standard Borel space:

A ∈ Σ11(X ) ⇔ ∃f : Y → X Borel ∃B ∈ B(Y ) f (B) = A So the isomorphism relation ' on XL is analytic, as a subset of XL2(but in general not Borel).

(57)

Borel sets in XL

However, the following holds:

Theorem (Miller)

Let G be a Polish group, X a standard Borel space, (g , x ) 7→ gx a Borel action of G on X .

Then every orbit {gx }g ∈G is Borel.

Definition

Lω1ω is the extension of L obtained by allowing countable disjunctions and conjunctions

nϕn, ∧nϕn

where each ϕnhas free variables between v0, . . . , vk−1 for some k independent of n (so each formula has finitely many free variables).

(58)

Borel sets in XL

However, the following holds:

Theorem (Miller)

Let G be a Polish group, X a standard Borel space, (g , x ) 7→ gx a Borel action of G on X . Then every orbit {gx }g ∈G is Borel.

Definition

Lω1ω is the extension of L obtained by allowing countable disjunctions and conjunctions

nϕn, ∧nϕn

where each ϕnhas free variables between v0, . . . , vk−1 for some k independent of n (so each formula has finitely many free variables).

(59)

Borel sets in XL

However, the following holds:

Theorem (Miller)

Let G be a Polish group, X a standard Borel space, (g , x ) 7→ gx a Borel action of G on X . Then every orbit {gx }g ∈G is Borel.

Definition

Lω1ωis the extension of L obtained by allowing countable disjunctions and conjunctions

nϕn, ∧nϕn

where each ϕnhas free variables between v0, . . . , vk−1 for some k independent of n (so each formula has finitely many free variables).

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

In this 11-year follow-up of the Casale Monferrato cohort of type 2 diabetic subjects we aimed to assess: (1) the long- term predictive role of AER, independently of conventional

assumption [mean and standard deviation (SD) equivalence]; the second Likert assumption or equal item–scale correla- tions (Pearson r: all items within a scale should contribute

In our view, the marketplace occurs when agents are involved in decentralised and anonymous exchanges, when the parties involved are informally organised and autonomous, when

with a subsequent fall in the number of individuals in the autumn and a new increase in population starting from February. An attempt to describe the size classes

Fifty years ago a proposal of urban reform in Italy by Aldo Natoli focused very well paradoxes and risks of an urban planning held hostage to the ground rent.. Now

Se la basilica costi- tuiva il fulcro della sezione meridionale dell’insieme, la parte del foro posta a nord della Mese (e dunque nella VII regione) era destinata ad accogliere

Estos y otros elementos, los del uso de las plantas, nos conducen a una construcción histórica que resalta el papel de las africanas y sus descendientes como

Nelle aree prossime alle strutture citate, sono stati individuati, tramite un sondino metallico, numerosissimi altri elementi lapidei di incerta attribuzione al di sotto di