• Non ci sono risultati.

Well quasi-orders, better quasi-orders, and classification problems in descriptive set theory

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Condividi "Well quasi-orders, better quasi-orders, and classification problems in descriptive set theory"

Copied!
132
0
0

Testo completo

(1)

Well quasi-orders, better quasi-orders, and classification problems in

descriptive set theory

(2)

(Very) general framework

I Descriptive set theory (DST) was founded by people like Baire, Borel, Lebesgue, Luzin, Suslin, Sierpinskpi and others in the first two decades of the XXth century. Scope: the study of the descriptive complexity of sets of real numbers.

I In the last few decades, there has been a lot of work to investigate the complexity of relations between real numbers, or elements of other standard Borel spaces.

I Somehow vague questions:

I

Are there any interesting relations — from the point of view of DST

— that turn out to be wqo?

I

Where do they come out?

I

What can be said about their complexity?

(3)

(Very) general framework

I Descriptive set theory (DST) was founded by people like Baire, Borel, Lebesgue, Luzin, Suslin, Sierpinskpi and others in the first two decades of the XXth century. Scope: the study of the descriptive complexity of sets of real numbers.

I In the last few decades, there has been a lot of work to investigate the complexity of relations between real numbers, or elements of other standard Borel spaces.

I Somehow vague questions:

I

Are there any interesting relations — from the point of view of DST

— that turn out to be wqo?

I

Where do they come out?

I

What can be said about their complexity?

(4)

(Very) general framework

I Descriptive set theory (DST) was founded by people like Baire, Borel, Lebesgue, Luzin, Suslin, Sierpinskpi and others in the first two decades of the XXth century. Scope: the study of the descriptive complexity of sets of real numbers.

I In the last few decades, there has been a lot of work to investigate the complexity of relations between real numbers, or elements of other standard Borel spaces.

I Somehow vague questions:

I

Are there any interesting relations — from the point of view of DST

— that turn out to be wqo?

I

Where do they come out?

I

What can be said about their complexity?

(5)

Scope of the talk

I will mainly concentrate on the second question: I will present a new

(surprisingly easy) example of a bqo that arose studying relations from a

DST perspective, and discuss some problem that stem from it.

(6)

A quick review of DST

Let X be a topological space.

Define the Borel hierarchy by induction on 1 ≤ α < ω 1 :

I Σ 0 1 (X ) = the family of all open subsets of X

I Π 0 α (X ) = {X \ A} A∈Σ

0 α

(X ) I Σ 0 α (X ) = S

n∈N C n , where C n ∈ Π 0 β

n

, β n < α, for α ≥ 2

I ∆ 0 α (X ) = Σ 0 α (X ) ∩ Π 0 α (X )

I B(X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Σ 0 α (X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Π 0 α (X ) = bigcup α∈ω

1

0 α (X ) B(X ) is the σ-algebra of Borel subsets of X . A function f : X → Y between topological spaces is Borel if

∀B ∈ B(X ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(Y ) or, equivalently,

∀B ∈ Σ 0 1 (Y ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(X )

(7)

A quick review of DST

Let X be a topological space. Define the Borel hierarchy by induction on 1 ≤ α < ω 1 :

I Σ 0 1 (X ) = the family of all open subsets of X

I Π 0 α (X ) = {X \ A} A∈Σ

0 α

(X ) I Σ 0 α (X ) = S

n∈N C n , where C n ∈ Π 0 β

n

, β n < α, for α ≥ 2

I ∆ 0 α (X ) = Σ 0 α (X ) ∩ Π 0 α (X )

I B(X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Σ 0 α (X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Π 0 α (X ) = bigcup α∈ω

1

0 α (X ) B(X ) is the σ-algebra of Borel subsets of X . A function f : X → Y between topological spaces is Borel if

∀B ∈ B(X ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(Y ) or, equivalently,

∀B ∈ Σ 0 1 (Y ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(X )

(8)

A quick review of DST

Let X be a topological space. Define the Borel hierarchy by induction on 1 ≤ α < ω 1 :

I Σ 0 1 (X ) = the family of all open subsets of X

I Π 0 α (X ) = {X \ A} A∈Σ

0 α

(X )

I Σ 0 α (X ) = S

n∈N C n , where C n ∈ Π 0 β

n

, β n < α, for α ≥ 2

I ∆ 0 α (X ) = Σ 0 α (X ) ∩ Π 0 α (X )

I B(X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Σ 0 α (X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Π 0 α (X ) = bigcup α∈ω

1

0 α (X ) B(X ) is the σ-algebra of Borel subsets of X . A function f : X → Y between topological spaces is Borel if

∀B ∈ B(X ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(Y ) or, equivalently,

∀B ∈ Σ 0 1 (Y ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(X )

(9)

A quick review of DST

Let X be a topological space. Define the Borel hierarchy by induction on 1 ≤ α < ω 1 :

I Σ 0 1 (X ) = the family of all open subsets of X

I Π 0 α (X ) = {X \ A} A∈Σ

0 α

(X ) I Σ 0 α (X ) = S

n∈N C n , where C n ∈ Π 0 β

n

, β n < α, for α ≥ 2

I ∆ 0 α (X ) = Σ 0 α (X ) ∩ Π 0 α (X )

I B(X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Σ 0 α (X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Π 0 α (X ) = bigcup α∈ω

1

0 α (X ) B(X ) is the σ-algebra of Borel subsets of X . A function f : X → Y between topological spaces is Borel if

∀B ∈ B(X ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(Y ) or, equivalently,

∀B ∈ Σ 0 1 (Y ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(X )

(10)

A quick review of DST

Let X be a topological space. Define the Borel hierarchy by induction on 1 ≤ α < ω 1 :

I Σ 0 1 (X ) = the family of all open subsets of X

I Π 0 α (X ) = {X \ A} A∈Σ

0 α

(X ) I Σ 0 α (X ) = S

n∈N C n , where C n ∈ Π 0 β

n

, β n < α, for α ≥ 2

I ∆ 0 α (X ) = Σ 0 α (X ) ∩ Π 0 α (X )

I B(X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Σ 0 α (X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Π 0 α (X ) = bigcup α∈ω

1

0 α (X ) B(X ) is the σ-algebra of Borel subsets of X . A function f : X → Y between topological spaces is Borel if

∀B ∈ B(X ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(Y ) or, equivalently,

∀B ∈ Σ 0 1 (Y ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(X )

(11)

A quick review of DST

Let X be a topological space. Define the Borel hierarchy by induction on 1 ≤ α < ω 1 :

I Σ 0 1 (X ) = the family of all open subsets of X

I Π 0 α (X ) = {X \ A} A∈Σ

0 α

(X ) I Σ 0 α (X ) = S

n∈N C n , where C n ∈ Π 0 β

n

, β n < α, for α ≥ 2

I ∆ 0 α (X ) = Σ 0 α (X ) ∩ Π 0 α (X )

I B(X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Σ 0 α (X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Π 0 α (X ) = bigcup α∈ω

1

0 α (X )

B(X ) is the σ-algebra of Borel subsets of X . A function f : X → Y between topological spaces is Borel if

∀B ∈ B(X ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(Y ) or, equivalently,

∀B ∈ Σ 0 1 (Y ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(X )

(12)

A quick review of DST

Let X be a topological space. Define the Borel hierarchy by induction on 1 ≤ α < ω 1 :

I Σ 0 1 (X ) = the family of all open subsets of X

I Π 0 α (X ) = {X \ A} A∈Σ

0 α

(X ) I Σ 0 α (X ) = S

n∈N C n , where C n ∈ Π 0 β

n

, β n < α, for α ≥ 2

I ∆ 0 α (X ) = Σ 0 α (X ) ∩ Π 0 α (X )

I B(X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Σ 0 α (X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Π 0 α (X ) = bigcup α∈ω

1

0 α (X ) B(X ) is the σ-algebra of Borel subsets of X .

A function f : X → Y between topological spaces is Borel if

∀B ∈ B(X ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(Y ) or, equivalently,

∀B ∈ Σ 0 1 (Y ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(X )

(13)

A quick review of DST

Let X be a topological space. Define the Borel hierarchy by induction on 1 ≤ α < ω 1 :

I Σ 0 1 (X ) = the family of all open subsets of X

I Π 0 α (X ) = {X \ A} A∈Σ

0 α

(X ) I Σ 0 α (X ) = S

n∈N C n , where C n ∈ Π 0 β

n

, β n < α, for α ≥ 2

I ∆ 0 α (X ) = Σ 0 α (X ) ∩ Π 0 α (X )

I B(X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Σ 0 α (X ) = S

α∈ω

1

Π 0 α (X ) = bigcup α∈ω

1

0 α (X ) B(X ) is the σ-algebra of Borel subsets of X . A function f : X → Y between topological spaces is Borel if

∀B ∈ B(X ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(Y ) or, equivalently,

∀B ∈ Σ 0 1 (Y ) f −1 (B) ∈ B(X )

(14)

Polish and standard Borel spaces

A topological space is Polish if it is separable and completely metrisable.

For a Polish space X , the Borel hierarchy is increasing:

∀α, β ∈ ω 1 (α < β ⇒ Σ 0 α (X ) ∪ Π 0 α (X ) ⊆ ∆ 0 β (X ))

A standard Borel space is a set X endowed with a σ-algebra B(X ) that is the σ-algebra of Borel sets for some Polish topology on X .

If X is standard Borel and A ∈ B(X ), then A, with the induced

σ-algebra, is standard Borel as well.

(15)

Polish and standard Borel spaces

A topological space is Polish if it is separable and completely metrisable.

For a Polish space X , the Borel hierarchy is increasing:

∀α, β ∈ ω 1 (α < β ⇒ Σ 0 α (X ) ∪ Π 0 α (X ) ⊆ ∆ 0 β (X ))

A standard Borel space is a set X endowed with a σ-algebra B(X ) that is the σ-algebra of Borel sets for some Polish topology on X .

If X is standard Borel and A ∈ B(X ), then A, with the induced

σ-algebra, is standard Borel as well.

(16)

Polish and standard Borel spaces

A topological space is Polish if it is separable and completely metrisable.

For a Polish space X , the Borel hierarchy is increasing:

∀α, β ∈ ω 1 (α < β ⇒ Σ 0 α (X ) ∪ Π 0 α (X ) ⊆ ∆ 0 β (X ))

A standard Borel space is a set X endowed with a σ-algebra B(X ) that is the σ-algebra of Borel sets for some Polish topology on X .

If X is standard Borel and A ∈ B(X ), then A, with the induced

σ-algebra, is standard Borel as well.

(17)

Polish and standard Borel spaces

A topological space is Polish if it is separable and completely metrisable.

For a Polish space X , the Borel hierarchy is increasing:

∀α, β ∈ ω 1 (α < β ⇒ Σ 0 α (X ) ∪ Π 0 α (X ) ⊆ ∆ 0 β (X ))

A standard Borel space is a set X endowed with a σ-algebra B(X ) that is the σ-algebra of Borel sets for some Polish topology on X .

If X is standard Borel and A ∈ B(X ), then A, with the induced

σ-algebra, is standard Borel as well.

(18)

The projective hierarchy

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic (or Σ 1 1 ) if there are a standard Borel space Y and a Borel function f : Y → X such that A = imf .

Given the class Σ 1 n , let

I Π 1 n (X ) = {A ⊆ X | X \ A ∈ Σ 1 n (X )}

I Σ 1 n+1 (X ) = {A ⊆ X | ∃Y standard Borel, f : Y → X Borel, B ∈ Π 1 n (X ) A = f (B)}

I ∆ 1 n (X ) = Σ 1 n (X ) ∩ Π 1 n (X )

(19)

The projective hierarchy

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic (or Σ 1 1 ) if there are a standard Borel space Y and a Borel function f : Y → X such that A = imf .

Given the class Σ 1 n , let

I Π 1 n (X ) = {A ⊆ X | X \ A ∈ Σ 1 n (X )}

I Σ 1 n+1 (X ) = {A ⊆ X | ∃Y standard Borel, f : Y → X Borel, B ∈ Π 1 n (X ) A = f (B)}

I ∆ 1 n (X ) = Σ 1 n (X ) ∩ Π 1 n (X )

(20)

The projective hierarchy

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic (or Σ 1 1 ) if there are a standard Borel space Y and a Borel function f : Y → X such that A = imf .

Given the class Σ 1 n , let

I Π 1 n (X ) = {A ⊆ X | X \ A ∈ Σ 1 n (X )}

I Σ 1 n+1 (X ) = {A ⊆ X | ∃Y standard Borel, f : Y → X Borel, B ∈ Π 1 n (X ) A = f (B)}

I ∆ 1 n (X ) = Σ 1 n (X ) ∩ Π 1 n (X )

(21)

The projective hierarchy

A subset A of a standard Borel space X is analytic (or Σ 1 1 ) if there are a standard Borel space Y and a Borel function f : Y → X such that A = imf .

Given the class Σ 1 n , let

I Π 1 n (X ) = {A ⊆ X | X \ A ∈ Σ 1 n (X )}

I Σ 1 n+1 (X ) = {A ⊆ X | ∃Y standard Borel, f : Y → X Borel, B ∈ Π 1 n (X ) A = f (B)}

I ∆ 1 n (X ) = Σ 1 n (X ) ∩ Π 1 n (X )

(22)

A motivating example

A great amount of classes of mathematical objects can be given a natural standard Borel structure. Moreover, usual manipulations of such objects turn out to be Borel functions.

Example. Let L = {R i , f j , c k | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K } be a countable first-order language. If A is a countable set (usually A = N), the set of L-structures with universe A is (coded by) some element

x ∈ Y

i ∈I

2 A

ar (i )

× Y

j ∈J

A A

ar (j )

× A K = X L

X L is a Polish space under the product topology.

(23)

A motivating example

A great amount of classes of mathematical objects can be given a natural standard Borel structure. Moreover, usual manipulations of such objects turn out to be Borel functions.

Example. Let L = {R i , f j , c k | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K } be a countable first-order language.

If A is a countable set (usually A = N), the set of L-structures with universe A is (coded by) some element

x ∈ Y

i ∈I

2 A

ar (i )

× Y

j ∈J

A A

ar (j )

× A K = X L

X L is a Polish space under the product topology.

(24)

A motivating example

A great amount of classes of mathematical objects can be given a natural standard Borel structure. Moreover, usual manipulations of such objects turn out to be Borel functions.

Example. Let L = {R i , f j , c k | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K } be a countable first-order language. If A is a countable set (usually A = N), the set of L-structures with universe A is (coded by) some element

x ∈ Y

i ∈I

2 A

ar (i )

× Y

j ∈J

A A

ar (j )

× A K = X L

X L is a Polish space under the product topology.

(25)

A motivating example

A great amount of classes of mathematical objects can be given a natural standard Borel structure. Moreover, usual manipulations of such objects turn out to be Borel functions.

Example. Let L = {R i , f j , c k | i ∈ I , j ∈ J, k ∈ K } be a countable first-order language. If A is a countable set (usually A = N), the set of L-structures with universe A is (coded by) some element

x ∈ Y

i ∈I

2 A

ar (i )

× Y

j ∈J

A A

ar (j )

× A K = X L

X L is a Polish space under the product topology.

(26)

A motivating example

The Polish group Sym(A) acts on X L by the logic action: for g ∈ Sym(A), x ∈ X L , the model gx is obtained from model x by permutating the elements of A by g .

Theorem. (Lopez-Escobar) The Borel subsets of X L that are invariant under the logic action are exacly the sets of the form

B ϕ = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ} for some L ω

1

ω -sentence ϕ.

Example. Let L = {≤}, where ≤ is a binary relation symbol, so that X L = 2 N

2

. Let ϕ be an axiom for linear orders.Then

LO = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

is a Borel (actually closed) subset of X L .

(27)

A motivating example

The Polish group Sym(A) acts on X L by the logic action: for g ∈ Sym(A), x ∈ X L , the model gx is obtained from model x by permutating the elements of A by g .

Theorem. (Lopez-Escobar) The Borel subsets of X L that are invariant under the logic action are exacly the sets of the form

B ϕ = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

for some L ω

1

ω -sentence ϕ.

Example. Let L = {≤}, where ≤ is a binary relation symbol, so that X L = 2 N

2

. Let ϕ be an axiom for linear orders.Then

LO = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

is a Borel (actually closed) subset of X L .

(28)

A motivating example

The Polish group Sym(A) acts on X L by the logic action: for g ∈ Sym(A), x ∈ X L , the model gx is obtained from model x by permutating the elements of A by g .

Theorem. (Lopez-Escobar) The Borel subsets of X L that are invariant under the logic action are exacly the sets of the form

B ϕ = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

for some L ω

1

ω -sentence ϕ.

Example. Let L = {≤}, where ≤ is a binary relation symbol, so that X L = 2 N

2

.

Let ϕ be an axiom for linear orders.Then

LO = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

is a Borel (actually closed) subset of X L .

(29)

A motivating example

The Polish group Sym(A) acts on X L by the logic action: for g ∈ Sym(A), x ∈ X L , the model gx is obtained from model x by permutating the elements of A by g .

Theorem. (Lopez-Escobar) The Borel subsets of X L that are invariant under the logic action are exacly the sets of the form

B ϕ = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

for some L ω

1

ω -sentence ϕ.

Example. Let L = {≤}, where ≤ is a binary relation symbol, so that X L = 2 N

2

. Let ϕ be an axiom for linear orders.

Then

LO = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

is a Borel (actually closed) subset of X L .

(30)

A motivating example

The Polish group Sym(A) acts on X L by the logic action: for g ∈ Sym(A), x ∈ X L , the model gx is obtained from model x by permutating the elements of A by g .

Theorem. (Lopez-Escobar) The Borel subsets of X L that are invariant under the logic action are exacly the sets of the form

B ϕ = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

for some L ω

1

ω -sentence ϕ.

Example. Let L = {≤}, where ≤ is a binary relation symbol, so that X L = 2 N

2

. Let ϕ be an axiom for linear orders.Then

LO = {x ∈ X L | x |= ϕ}

is a Borel (actually closed) subset of X L .

(31)

Borel reducibility

Let E , F be n-ary relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , respectively.

Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted E ≤ B F if there is a Borel function f : X → Y such that

∀x 1 , . . . , x n ∈ X (E (x 1 , . . . , x n ) ⇔ F (f (x 1 ), . . . , f (x n )))

Main examples for classes of countable structures: Analytic

equivalence relations, like isomorphism or bi-embeddability in some

classes of countable structures. Analytic quasi-orders, like embeddability.

(32)

Borel reducibility

Let E , F be n-ary relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , respectively.

Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted E ≤ B F if there is a Borel function f : X → Y such that

∀x 1 , . . . , x n ∈ X (E (x 1 , . . . , x n ) ⇔ F (f (x 1 ), . . . , f (x n )))

Main examples for classes of countable structures: Analytic

equivalence relations, like isomorphism or bi-embeddability in some

classes of countable structures. Analytic quasi-orders, like embeddability.

(33)

Borel reducibility

Let E , F be n-ary relations on standard Borel spaces X , Y , respectively.

Then E is Borel reducible to F , denoted E ≤ B F if there is a Borel function f : X → Y such that

∀x 1 , . . . , x n ∈ X (E (x 1 , . . . , x n ) ⇔ F (f (x 1 ), . . . , f (x n )))

Main examples for classes of countable structures: Analytic

equivalence relations, like isomorphism or bi-embeddability in some

classes of countable structures. Analytic quasi-orders, like embeddability.

(34)

Completeness

If R is a class of relations on standard Borel spaces, then a relation F is R-complete if

1. F ∈ R

2. ∀E ∈ R E ≤ B F

Questions:

I Does R admit complete elements? Who are them?

I What is the complexity, both in the Borel hierarchy and w.r.t. ≤ B ,

of the elements of R?

(35)

Completeness

If R is a class of relations on standard Borel spaces, then a relation F is R-complete if

1. F ∈ R

2. ∀E ∈ R E ≤ B F Questions:

I Does R admit complete elements? Who are them?

I What is the complexity, both in the Borel hierarchy and w.r.t. ≤ B ,

of the elements of R?

(36)

Completeness

If R is a class of relations on standard Borel spaces, then a relation F is R-complete if

1. F ∈ R

2. ∀E ∈ R E ≤ B F Questions:

I Does R admit complete elements? Who are them?

I What is the complexity, both in the Borel hierarchy and w.r.t. ≤ B ,

of the elements of R?

(37)

Completeness

Several classes of relations have be proven to admit complete elements.

Examples:

I Borel equivalence relations with at most countable classes. A complete element is the orbit equivalence relation of F 2 on 2 F

2

.

I Isomorphism relations for countable structures. A complete element is isomorphism on countable graphs.

I Analytic quasi-orders. A complete element is embeddability on countable graphs.

I Analytic equivalence relations. A complete element is bi-embeddability on countable graphs.

Remark. An R-complete relation must be sufficiently complex both

w.r.t. the projective hierarchy and combinatorially, since it Borel embeds

every element of R. In particular, a wqo cannot be R-complete, unless

all elements of R are wqo’s.

(38)

Completeness

Several classes of relations have be proven to admit complete elements.

Examples:

I Borel equivalence relations with at most countable classes. A complete element is the orbit equivalence relation of F 2 on 2 F

2

.

I Isomorphism relations for countable structures. A complete element is isomorphism on countable graphs.

I Analytic quasi-orders. A complete element is embeddability on countable graphs.

I Analytic equivalence relations. A complete element is bi-embeddability on countable graphs.

Remark. An R-complete relation must be sufficiently complex both

w.r.t. the projective hierarchy and combinatorially, since it Borel embeds

every element of R. In particular, a wqo cannot be R-complete, unless

all elements of R are wqo’s.

(39)

Completeness

Several classes of relations have be proven to admit complete elements.

Examples:

I Borel equivalence relations with at most countable classes. A complete element is the orbit equivalence relation of F 2 on 2 F

2

.

I Isomorphism relations for countable structures. A complete element is isomorphism on countable graphs.

I Analytic quasi-orders. A complete element is embeddability on countable graphs.

I Analytic equivalence relations. A complete element is bi-embeddability on countable graphs.

Remark. An R-complete relation must be sufficiently complex both

w.r.t. the projective hierarchy and combinatorially, since it Borel embeds

every element of R. In particular, a wqo cannot be R-complete, unless

all elements of R are wqo’s.

(40)

Completeness

Several classes of relations have be proven to admit complete elements.

Examples:

I Borel equivalence relations with at most countable classes. A complete element is the orbit equivalence relation of F 2 on 2 F

2

.

I Isomorphism relations for countable structures. A complete element is isomorphism on countable graphs.

I Analytic quasi-orders. A complete element is embeddability on countable graphs.

I Analytic equivalence relations. A complete element is bi-embeddability on countable graphs.

Remark. An R-complete relation must be sufficiently complex both

w.r.t. the projective hierarchy and combinatorially, since it Borel embeds

every element of R. In particular, a wqo cannot be R-complete, unless

all elements of R are wqo’s.

(41)

Completeness

Several classes of relations have be proven to admit complete elements.

Examples:

I Borel equivalence relations with at most countable classes. A complete element is the orbit equivalence relation of F 2 on 2 F

2

.

I Isomorphism relations for countable structures. A complete element is isomorphism on countable graphs.

I Analytic quasi-orders. A complete element is embeddability on countable graphs.

I Analytic equivalence relations. A complete element is bi-embeddability on countable graphs.

Remark. An R-complete relation must be sufficiently complex both w.r.t. the projective hierarchy and combinatorially, since it Borel embeds every element of R.

In particular, a wqo cannot be R-complete, unless

all elements of R are wqo’s.

(42)

Completeness

Several classes of relations have be proven to admit complete elements.

Examples:

I Borel equivalence relations with at most countable classes. A complete element is the orbit equivalence relation of F 2 on 2 F

2

.

I Isomorphism relations for countable structures. A complete element is isomorphism on countable graphs.

I Analytic quasi-orders. A complete element is embeddability on countable graphs.

I Analytic equivalence relations. A complete element is bi-embeddability on countable graphs.

Remark. An R-complete relation must be sufficiently complex both

w.r.t. the projective hierarchy and combinatorially, since it Borel embeds

every element of R. In particular, a wqo cannot be R-complete, unless

all elements of R are wqo’s.

(43)

Relations on countable linear orders

In the space LO several relations of interest are defined.

1. Isomorphism

Theorem. (Friedman, Stanley, 1989) The relation of isomorphism on countable linear orders is complete for the class of isomorphim relations on countable structures.

2. Recursive isomorphim

Theorem. (C., 2002) The relation of recursive isomorphism on countable

linear orders is complete for Borel equivalence relations with at most

countable classes.

(44)

Relations on countable linear orders

In the space LO several relations of interest are defined.

1. Isomorphism

Theorem. (Friedman, Stanley, 1989) The relation of isomorphism on countable linear orders is complete for the class of isomorphim relations on countable structures.

2. Recursive isomorphim

Theorem. (C., 2002) The relation of recursive isomorphism on countable

linear orders is complete for Borel equivalence relations with at most

countable classes.

(45)

Relations on countable linear orders

In the space LO several relations of interest are defined.

1. Isomorphism

Theorem. (Friedman, Stanley, 1989) The relation of isomorphism on countable linear orders is complete for the class of isomorphim relations on countable structures.

2. Recursive isomorphim

Theorem. (C., 2002) The relation of recursive isomorphism on countable

linear orders is complete for Borel equivalence relations with at most

countable classes.

(46)

Relations on countable linear orders

In the space LO several relations of interest are defined.

1. Isomorphism

Theorem. (Friedman, Stanley, 1989) The relation of isomorphism on countable linear orders is complete for the class of isomorphim relations on countable structures.

2. Recursive isomorphim

Theorem. (C., 2002) The relation of recursive isomorphism on countable

linear orders is complete for Borel equivalence relations with at most

countable classes.

(47)

Relations on countable linear orders

In the space LO several relations of interest are defined.

1. Isomorphism

Theorem. (Friedman, Stanley, 1989) The relation of isomorphism on countable linear orders is complete for the class of isomorphim relations on countable structures.

2. Recursive isomorphim

Theorem. (C., 2002) The relation of recursive isomorphism on countable

linear orders is complete for Borel equivalence relations with at most

countable classes.

(48)

Relations on countable linear orders

3. Embeddability

The relation on embeddability ≤ i on LO is an analytic, non-Borel, quasi-order. However, it is very far from being complete in this class. Theorem. (Laver, 1971) The relation of embeddability on countable linear orders (in fact on σ-scattered ones) is a bqo.

4. Continuous embeddability

Denote by ≤ c the relation of continuous order preserving embeddability between linear orders.

Theorem. (van Engelen, Miller, Steel, 1987) The relation ≤ c on countable linear orders is a bqo.

The results proved by Laver and by van Engelen, Miller, and Steel are

actually stronger.

(49)

Relations on countable linear orders

3. Embeddability

The relation on embeddability ≤ i on LO is an analytic, non-Borel, quasi-order.

However, it is very far from being complete in this class. Theorem. (Laver, 1971) The relation of embeddability on countable linear orders (in fact on σ-scattered ones) is a bqo.

4. Continuous embeddability

Denote by ≤ c the relation of continuous order preserving embeddability between linear orders.

Theorem. (van Engelen, Miller, Steel, 1987) The relation ≤ c on countable linear orders is a bqo.

The results proved by Laver and by van Engelen, Miller, and Steel are

actually stronger.

(50)

Relations on countable linear orders

3. Embeddability

The relation on embeddability ≤ i on LO is an analytic, non-Borel, quasi-order. However, it is very far from being complete in this class.

Theorem. (Laver, 1971) The relation of embeddability on countable linear orders (in fact on σ-scattered ones) is a bqo.

4. Continuous embeddability

Denote by ≤ c the relation of continuous order preserving embeddability between linear orders.

Theorem. (van Engelen, Miller, Steel, 1987) The relation ≤ c on countable linear orders is a bqo.

The results proved by Laver and by van Engelen, Miller, and Steel are

actually stronger.

(51)

Relations on countable linear orders

3. Embeddability

The relation on embeddability ≤ i on LO is an analytic, non-Borel, quasi-order. However, it is very far from being complete in this class.

Theorem. (Laver, 1971) The relation of embeddability on countable linear orders (in fact on σ-scattered ones) is a bqo.

4. Continuous embeddability

Denote by ≤ c the relation of continuous order preserving embeddability between linear orders.

Theorem. (van Engelen, Miller, Steel, 1987) The relation ≤ c on countable linear orders is a bqo.

The results proved by Laver and by van Engelen, Miller, and Steel are

actually stronger.

(52)

Relations on countable linear orders

3. Embeddability

The relation on embeddability ≤ i on LO is an analytic, non-Borel, quasi-order. However, it is very far from being complete in this class.

Theorem. (Laver, 1971) The relation of embeddability on countable linear orders (in fact on σ-scattered ones) is a bqo.

4. Continuous embeddability

Denote by ≤ c the relation of continuous order preserving embeddability between linear orders.

Theorem. (van Engelen, Miller, Steel, 1987) The relation ≤ c on countable linear orders is a bqo.

The results proved by Laver and by van Engelen, Miller, and Steel are

actually stronger.

(53)

Relations on countable linear orders

3. Embeddability

The relation on embeddability ≤ i on LO is an analytic, non-Borel, quasi-order. However, it is very far from being complete in this class.

Theorem. (Laver, 1971) The relation of embeddability on countable linear orders (in fact on σ-scattered ones) is a bqo.

4. Continuous embeddability

Denote by ≤ c the relation of continuous order preserving embeddability between linear orders.

Theorem. (van Engelen, Miller, Steel, 1987) The relation ≤ c on countable linear orders is a bqo.

The results proved by Laver and by van Engelen, Miller, and Steel are

actually stronger.

(54)

Preserving bqo’s

Definition. (Louveau, Saint Raymond, 1990) Let C be a class of structures with morphisms between them, such that the identities are C-morphisms, and C-morphisms are closed under composition.

Given a quasi-order Q, let

Q C = {f : domf → Q | domf ∈ C} quasi-ordered by

f 0 ≤ f 1 ⇔∃g : domf 0 → domf 1 a C-morphism

∀x ∈ domf 0 f 0 (x ) ≤ Q f 1 g (x )

Class C preserves bqo’s if whenever Q is a bqo, then Q C is bqo as well.

(55)

Preserving bqo’s

Definition. (Louveau, Saint Raymond, 1990) Let C be a class of structures with morphisms between them, such that the identities are C-morphisms, and C-morphisms are closed under composition.

Given a quasi-order Q, let

Q C = {f : domf → Q | domf ∈ C}

quasi-ordered by

f 0 ≤ f 1 ⇔∃g : domf 0 → domf 1 a C-morphism

∀x ∈ domf 0 f 0 (x ) ≤ Q f 1 g (x )

Class C preserves bqo’s if whenever Q is a bqo, then Q C is bqo as well.

(56)

Preserving bqo’s

Definition. (Louveau, Saint Raymond, 1990) Let C be a class of structures with morphisms between them, such that the identities are C-morphisms, and C-morphisms are closed under composition.

Given a quasi-order Q, let

Q C = {f : domf → Q | domf ∈ C}

quasi-ordered by

f 0 ≤ f 1 ⇔∃g : domf 0 → domf 1 a C-morphism

∀x ∈ domf 0 f 0 (x ) ≤ Q f 1 g (x )

Class C preserves bqo’s if whenever Q is a bqo, then Q C is bqo as well.

(57)

Preserving bqo’s

Definition. (Louveau, Saint Raymond, 1990) Let C be a class of structures with morphisms between them, such that the identities are C-morphisms, and C-morphisms are closed under composition.

Given a quasi-order Q, let

Q C = {f : domf → Q | domf ∈ C}

quasi-ordered by

f 0 ≤ f 1 ⇔∃g : domf 0 → domf 1 a C-morphism

∀x ∈ domf 0 f 0 (x ) ≤ Q f 1 g (x )

Class C preserves bqo’s if whenever Q is a bqo, then Q C is bqo as well.

(58)

Preserving bqo’s

Theorem. (Laver, 1971) The class of σ-scattered linear orders under ≤ i preserves bqo’s.

Theorem. (van Engelen, Miller, Steel, 1987) The class of countable

linear orders under ≤ c preserve bqo’s.

(59)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

5. Epimorphisms

(Carroy, Marcone, C., in progress)

Given linear orders L, K , let K ≤ s L if there is an order preserving surjection f : L → K :

∀x, y ∈ L (x ≤ L y ⇒ g (x ) ≤ K g (y ))

The restriction of ≤ s to LO is an analytic quasi-order.

(60)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

5. Epimorphisms (Carroy, Marcone, C., in progress)

Given linear orders L, K , let K ≤ s L if there is an order preserving surjection f : L → K :

∀x, y ∈ L (x ≤ L y ⇒ g (x ) ≤ K g (y ))

The restriction of ≤ s to LO is an analytic quasi-order.

(61)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

5. Epimorphisms (Carroy, Marcone, C., in progress)

Given linear orders L, K , let K ≤ s L if there is an order preserving surjection f : L → K :

∀x, y ∈ L (x ≤ L y ⇒ g (x ) ≤ K g (y ))

The restriction of ≤ s to LO is an analytic quasi-order.

(62)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

5. Epimorphisms (Carroy, Marcone, C., in progress)

Given linear orders L, K , let K ≤ s L if there is an order preserving surjection f : L → K :

∀x, y ∈ L (x ≤ L y ⇒ g (x ) ≤ K g (y ))

The restriction of ≤ s to LO is an analytic quasi-order.

(63)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

Some easy remarks:

I If f : L → K witnesses K ≤ s L, then f has a right inverse g : K → L witnessing K ≤ i L. So ≤ s ⊆≤ i . The converse does not hold, e.g., ω, ω + 1.

I K ≤ s L if and only if L = P

i ∈K L i .

I If L has a minimum (or a maximum), while K does not, then K  L.

I If K , L do not have maximum and K ≤ s L, then cof (K ) = cof (L). Similarly for orders without minimum.

As a first consequence, an analogous of Laver’s result cannot hold for ≤ s :

if κ, λ are distinct infinite cardinals, they are incomparable under ≤ s .

(64)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

Some easy remarks:

I If f : L → K witnesses K ≤ s L, then f has a right inverse g : K → L witnessing K ≤ i L. So ≤ s ⊆≤ i .

The converse does not hold, e.g., ω, ω + 1.

I K ≤ s L if and only if L = P

i ∈K L i .

I If L has a minimum (or a maximum), while K does not, then K  L.

I If K , L do not have maximum and K ≤ s L, then cof (K ) = cof (L). Similarly for orders without minimum.

As a first consequence, an analogous of Laver’s result cannot hold for ≤ s :

if κ, λ are distinct infinite cardinals, they are incomparable under ≤ s .

(65)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

Some easy remarks:

I If f : L → K witnesses K ≤ s L, then f has a right inverse g : K → L witnessing K ≤ i L. So ≤ s ⊆≤ i . The converse does not hold, e.g., ω, ω + 1.

I K ≤ s L if and only if L = P

i ∈K L i .

I If L has a minimum (or a maximum), while K does not, then K  L.

I If K , L do not have maximum and K ≤ s L, then cof (K ) = cof (L). Similarly for orders without minimum.

As a first consequence, an analogous of Laver’s result cannot hold for ≤ s :

if κ, λ are distinct infinite cardinals, they are incomparable under ≤ s .

(66)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

Some easy remarks:

I If f : L → K witnesses K ≤ s L, then f has a right inverse g : K → L witnessing K ≤ i L. So ≤ s ⊆≤ i . The converse does not hold, e.g., ω, ω + 1.

I K ≤ s L if and only if L = P

i ∈K L i .

I If L has a minimum (or a maximum), while K does not, then K  L.

I If K , L do not have maximum and K ≤ s L, then cof (K ) = cof (L). Similarly for orders without minimum.

As a first consequence, an analogous of Laver’s result cannot hold for ≤ s :

if κ, λ are distinct infinite cardinals, they are incomparable under ≤ s .

(67)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

Some easy remarks:

I If f : L → K witnesses K ≤ s L, then f has a right inverse g : K → L witnessing K ≤ i L. So ≤ s ⊆≤ i . The converse does not hold, e.g., ω, ω + 1.

I K ≤ s L if and only if L = P

i ∈K L i .

I If L has a minimum (or a maximum), while K does not, then K  L.

I If K , L do not have maximum and K ≤ s L, then cof (K ) = cof (L). Similarly for orders without minimum.

As a first consequence, an analogous of Laver’s result cannot hold for ≤ s :

if κ, λ are distinct infinite cardinals, they are incomparable under ≤ s .

(68)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

Some easy remarks:

I If f : L → K witnesses K ≤ s L, then f has a right inverse g : K → L witnessing K ≤ i L. So ≤ s ⊆≤ i . The converse does not hold, e.g., ω, ω + 1.

I K ≤ s L if and only if L = P

i ∈K L i .

I If L has a minimum (or a maximum), while K does not, then K  L.

I If K , L do not have maximum and K ≤ s L, then cof (K ) = cof (L).

Similarly for orders without minimum.

As a first consequence, an analogous of Laver’s result cannot hold for ≤ s :

if κ, λ are distinct infinite cardinals, they are incomparable under ≤ s .

(69)

Epimorphisms on linear orders

Some easy remarks:

I If f : L → K witnesses K ≤ s L, then f has a right inverse g : K → L witnessing K ≤ i L. So ≤ s ⊆≤ i . The converse does not hold, e.g., ω, ω + 1.

I K ≤ s L if and only if L = P

i ∈K L i .

I If L has a minimum (or a maximum), while K does not, then K  L.

I If K , L do not have maximum and K ≤ s L, then cof (K ) = cof (L).

Similarly for orders without minimum.

As a first consequence, an analogous of Laver’s result cannot hold for ≤ s :

if κ, λ are distinct infinite cardinals, they are incomparable under ≤ s .

(70)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Lemma

If K has minimum, maximum, and it is complete, then for any order L, K ≤ i L ⇒ K ≤ s L

Proof.

If f : K ≤ i L and a = min K , define g : L → K by g (y ) =

 a if y < f (a)

sup{x ∈ K | f (x ) ≤ y } if y ≥ f (a)

Corollary

≤ s is a bqo on countable complete linear orders with maximum and

minimum.

(71)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Lemma

If K has minimum, maximum, and it is complete, then for any order L, K ≤ i L ⇒ K ≤ s L

Proof.

If f : K ≤ i L and a = min K , define g : L → K by g (y ) =

 a if y < f (a)

sup{x ∈ K | f (x ) ≤ y } if y ≥ f (a)

Corollary

≤ s is a bqo on countable complete linear orders with maximum and

minimum.

(72)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Lemma

If K has minimum, maximum, and it is complete, then for any order L, K ≤ i L ⇒ K ≤ s L

Proof.

If f : K ≤ i L and a = min K , define g : L → K by g (y ) =

 a if y < f (a)

sup{x ∈ K | f (x ) ≤ y } if y ≥ f (a)

Corollary

≤ s is a bqo on countable complete linear orders with maximum and

minimum.

(73)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Let LIN 3 be the class of all linear orders coloured in three colours: an element of LIN 3 is a linear order L together with a function c : L → 3.

LIN 3 can be quasi-ordered as follows: given

K = (K , c), L = (L, c 0 ) ∈ LIN 3

set

(K , c) ≤ col (L, c 0 ) ⇔∃f : K → L injective, order preserving, continuous,

and such that ∀x ∈ K c(x ) = c 0 f (x ) So (LIN 3 , ≤ col ) is 3 (LIN,≤

c

) in the notation of Louveau and Saint Raymond.

By the theorem of van Engelen, Miller, Steel, ≤ col is a bqo on the

subclass of LIN 3 consisting of countable orders.

(74)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Let LIN 3 be the class of all linear orders coloured in three colours: an element of LIN 3 is a linear order L together with a function c : L → 3.

LIN 3 can be quasi-ordered as follows: given

K = (K , c), L = (L, c 0 ) ∈ LIN 3

set

(K , c) ≤ col (L, c 0 ) ⇔∃f : K → L injective, order preserving, continuous,

and such that ∀x ∈ K c(x ) = c 0 f (x )

So (LIN 3 , ≤ col ) is 3 (LIN,≤

c

) in the notation of Louveau and Saint Raymond.

By the theorem of van Engelen, Miller, Steel, ≤ col is a bqo on the

subclass of LIN 3 consisting of countable orders.

(75)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Let LIN 3 be the class of all linear orders coloured in three colours: an element of LIN 3 is a linear order L together with a function c : L → 3.

LIN 3 can be quasi-ordered as follows: given

K = (K , c), L = (L, c 0 ) ∈ LIN 3

set

(K , c) ≤ col (L, c 0 ) ⇔∃f : K → L injective, order preserving, continuous,

and such that ∀x ∈ K c(x ) = c 0 f (x ) So (LIN 3 , ≤ col ) is 3 (LIN,≤

c

) in the notation of Louveau and Saint Raymond.

By the theorem of van Engelen, Miller, Steel, ≤ col is a bqo on the

subclass of LIN 3 consisting of countable orders.

(76)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Let LIN 3 be the class of all linear orders coloured in three colours: an element of LIN 3 is a linear order L together with a function c : L → 3.

LIN 3 can be quasi-ordered as follows: given

K = (K , c), L = (L, c 0 ) ∈ LIN 3

set

(K , c) ≤ col (L, c 0 ) ⇔∃f : K → L injective, order preserving, continuous,

and such that ∀x ∈ K c(x ) = c 0 f (x ) So (LIN 3 , ≤ col ) is 3 (LIN,≤

c

) in the notation of Louveau and Saint Raymond.

By the theorem of van Engelen, Miller, Steel, ≤ col is a bqo on the

subclass of LIN 3 consisting of countable orders.

(77)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Given a linear order L let its closure ¯ L be defined by completing L and then possibly adding a first or a last element, in case L does not have them.

The complete colouring of L is the map c L : ¯ L → 3 defined by

c L (x ) =

2 if x ∈ L

1 if x ∈ {min ¯ L, max ¯ L} and x / ∈ L 0 otherwise

So (¯ L, c L ) ∈ LIN 3 .

Notice that if L is countable, then L is scattered if and only if ¯ L is

countable.

(78)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Given a linear order L let its closure ¯ L be defined by completing L and then possibly adding a first or a last element, in case L does not have them. The complete colouring of L is the map c L : ¯ L → 3 defined by

c L (x ) =

2 if x ∈ L

1 if x ∈ {min ¯ L, max ¯ L} and x / ∈ L 0 otherwise

So (¯ L, c L ) ∈ LIN 3 .

Notice that if L is countable, then L is scattered if and only if ¯ L is

countable.

(79)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Given a linear order L let its closure ¯ L be defined by completing L and then possibly adding a first or a last element, in case L does not have them. The complete colouring of L is the map c L : ¯ L → 3 defined by

c L (x ) =

2 if x ∈ L

1 if x ∈ {min ¯ L, max ¯ L} and x / ∈ L 0 otherwise

So (¯ L, c L ) ∈ LIN 3 .

Notice that if L is countable, then L is scattered if and only if ¯ L is

countable.

(80)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Given a linear order L let its closure ¯ L be defined by completing L and then possibly adding a first or a last element, in case L does not have them. The complete colouring of L is the map c L : ¯ L → 3 defined by

c L (x ) =

2 if x ∈ L

1 if x ∈ {min ¯ L, max ¯ L} and x / ∈ L 0 otherwise

So (¯ L, c L ) ∈ LIN 3 .

Notice that if L is countable, then L is scattered if and only if ¯ L is

countable.

(81)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Lemma

Given linear orders K , L, if c K ≤ col c L , then K ≤ s L.

From this one gets

Theorem

≤ s is a bqo on scattered countable linear orders.

Proof.

If L is countable scattered, then ¯ L is countable. By the above lemma, the map Φ : K 7→ c K satisfies

Φ(K ) ≤ col Φ(L) ⇒ K ≤ s L

Since ≤ col is a bqo on countable orders, ≤ s is a bqo on scattered

countable orders.

(82)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Lemma

Given linear orders K , L, if c K ≤ col c L , then K ≤ s L.

From this one gets

Theorem

≤ s is a bqo on scattered countable linear orders.

Proof.

If L is countable scattered, then ¯ L is countable. By the above lemma, the map Φ : K 7→ c K satisfies

Φ(K ) ≤ col Φ(L) ⇒ K ≤ s L

Since ≤ col is a bqo on countable orders, ≤ s is a bqo on scattered

countable orders.

(83)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Lemma

Given linear orders K , L, if c K ≤ col c L , then K ≤ s L.

From this one gets

Theorem

≤ s is a bqo on scattered countable linear orders.

Proof.

If L is countable scattered, then ¯ L is countable.

By the above lemma, the map Φ : K 7→ c K satisfies

Φ(K ) ≤ col Φ(L) ⇒ K ≤ s L

Since ≤ col is a bqo on countable orders, ≤ s is a bqo on scattered

countable orders.

(84)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Lemma

Given linear orders K , L, if c K ≤ col c L , then K ≤ s L.

From this one gets

Theorem

≤ s is a bqo on scattered countable linear orders.

Proof.

If L is countable scattered, then ¯ L is countable. By the above lemma, the map Φ : K 7→ c K satisfies

Φ(K ) ≤ col Φ(L) ⇒ K ≤ s L

Since ≤ col is a bqo on countable orders, ≤ s is a bqo on scattered

countable orders.

(85)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Lemma

Given linear orders K , L, if c K ≤ col c L , then K ≤ s L.

From this one gets

Theorem

≤ s is a bqo on scattered countable linear orders.

Proof.

If L is countable scattered, then ¯ L is countable. By the above lemma, the map Φ : K 7→ c K satisfies

Φ(K ) ≤ col Φ(L) ⇒ K ≤ s L

Since ≤ col is a bqo on countable orders, ≤ s is a bqo on scattered

countable orders.

(86)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

It remains to consider non-scattered countable orders.

If L is a countable, non-scattered linear ordering, there are four mutually disjoint possibilities, depending on the existence of scattered initial or final tails:

1. η ≤ s L

2. L = L 0 + ˆ L, for some unique L 0 , ˆ L, with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 3. L = ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 1 , ˆ L, with L 1 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 4. L = L 0 + ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 0 , L 1 , ˆ L, with L 0 , L 1 scattered and

η ≤ s ˆ L

It remains to show that ≤ s is a bqo on each of these four classes.

The orders in case 1 are all ≤ s -equivalent.

(87)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

It remains to consider non-scattered countable orders. If L is a countable, non-scattered linear ordering, there are four mutually disjoint possibilities, depending on the existence of scattered initial or final tails:

1. η ≤ s L

2. L = L 0 + ˆ L, for some unique L 0 , ˆ L, with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 3. L = ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 1 , ˆ L, with L 1 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 4. L = L 0 + ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 0 , L 1 , ˆ L, with L 0 , L 1 scattered and

η ≤ s ˆ L

It remains to show that ≤ s is a bqo on each of these four classes.

The orders in case 1 are all ≤ s -equivalent.

(88)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

It remains to consider non-scattered countable orders. If L is a countable, non-scattered linear ordering, there are four mutually disjoint possibilities, depending on the existence of scattered initial or final tails:

1. η ≤ s L

2. L = L 0 + ˆ L, for some unique L 0 , ˆ L, with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 3. L = ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 1 , ˆ L, with L 1 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 4. L = L 0 + ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 0 , L 1 , ˆ L, with L 0 , L 1 scattered and

η ≤ s ˆ L

It remains to show that ≤ s is a bqo on each of these four classes.

The orders in case 1 are all ≤ s -equivalent.

(89)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

It remains to consider non-scattered countable orders. If L is a countable, non-scattered linear ordering, there are four mutually disjoint possibilities, depending on the existence of scattered initial or final tails:

1. η ≤ s L

2. L = L 0 + ˆ L, for some unique L 0 , ˆ L, with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L

3. L = ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 1 , ˆ L, with L 1 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 4. L = L 0 + ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 0 , L 1 , ˆ L, with L 0 , L 1 scattered and

η ≤ s ˆ L

It remains to show that ≤ s is a bqo on each of these four classes.

The orders in case 1 are all ≤ s -equivalent.

(90)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

It remains to consider non-scattered countable orders. If L is a countable, non-scattered linear ordering, there are four mutually disjoint possibilities, depending on the existence of scattered initial or final tails:

1. η ≤ s L

2. L = L 0 + ˆ L, for some unique L 0 , ˆ L, with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 3. L = ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 1 , ˆ L, with L 1 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 4. L = L 0 + ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 0 , L 1 , ˆ L, with L 0 , L 1 scattered and

η ≤ s ˆ L

It remains to show that ≤ s is a bqo on each of these four classes.

The orders in case 1 are all ≤ s -equivalent.

(91)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

It remains to consider non-scattered countable orders. If L is a countable, non-scattered linear ordering, there are four mutually disjoint possibilities, depending on the existence of scattered initial or final tails:

1. η ≤ s L

2. L = L 0 + ˆ L, for some unique L 0 , ˆ L, with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 3. L = ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 1 , ˆ L, with L 1 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 4. L = L 0 + ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 0 , L 1 , ˆ L, with L 0 , L 1 scattered and

η ≤ s ˆ L

It remains to show that ≤ s is a bqo on each of these four classes.

The orders in case 1 are all ≤ s -equivalent.

(92)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

It remains to consider non-scattered countable orders. If L is a countable, non-scattered linear ordering, there are four mutually disjoint possibilities, depending on the existence of scattered initial or final tails:

1. η ≤ s L

2. L = L 0 + ˆ L, for some unique L 0 , ˆ L, with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 3. L = ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 1 , ˆ L, with L 1 scattered and η ≤ s ˆ L 4. L = L 0 + ˆ L + L 1 , for some unique L 0 , L 1 , ˆ L, with L 0 , L 1 scattered and

η ≤ s ˆ L

It remains to show that ≤ s is a bqo on each of these four classes.

The orders in case 1 are all ≤ s -equivalent.

(93)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Consider case 2, i.e., orders of the form L = L 0 + ˆ L with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s L (the remaining cases are similar).

For L, M in this class, one has

L 0 ≤ s M 0 ⇒ L ≤ s M

Since ≤ s is already being proved to be a bqo on countable scattered linear orders (previous theorem), the assignement L 7→ L 0 proves that ≤ s

is also a bqo on this class.

(94)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Consider case 2, i.e., orders of the form L = L 0 + ˆ L with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s L (the remaining cases are similar).

For L, M in this class, one has

L 0 ≤ s M 0 ⇒ L ≤ s M

Since ≤ s is already being proved to be a bqo on countable scattered linear orders (previous theorem), the assignement L 7→ L 0 proves that ≤ s

is also a bqo on this class.

(95)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Consider case 2, i.e., orders of the form L = L 0 + ˆ L with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s L (the remaining cases are similar).

For L, M in this class, one has

L 0 ≤ s M 0 ⇒ L ≤ s M

Since ≤ s is already being proved to be a bqo on countable scattered linear orders (previous theorem),

the assignement L 7→ L 0 proves that ≤ s

is also a bqo on this class.

(96)

The bqo ≤ s on countable orders

Consider case 2, i.e., orders of the form L = L 0 + ˆ L with L 0 scattered and η ≤ s L (the remaining cases are similar).

For L, M in this class, one has

L 0 ≤ s M 0 ⇒ L ≤ s M

Since ≤ s is already being proved to be a bqo on countable scattered linear orders (previous theorem), the assignement L 7→ L 0 proves that ≤ s

is also a bqo on this class.

Riferimenti

Documenti correlati

Ute ROSENHAHN-OHLMEIER diskutiert in ihrem Beitrag („Strategien und Charakter des Erzählers in Heinrichs Reinhart Fuchs“, S. 423-438) die Figur des Erzählers im Epos

Farhat, A variational multiscale method for the large eddy simulation of compressible turbulent flows on unstructured meshes- application to vortex shedding , Comput.. Koobus, A

Anche da un punto di vista del cablaggio e della trasmissione dell’informazione sono allo studio diversi mate- riali polimerici che in conseguenza di drogaggi chimici

Inoltre, aggiorna il file di configurazione dello Agent e invia un messaggio per informare tutti gli Aggregator della creazione di un nuovo Service Data.. Il

Capitolo IV - Cambiamento organizzativo e gestione delle risorse umane: il caso Agenzia delle Entrate 4.1 Il cambiamento nella e della Pubblica Amministrazione italiana 4.2 Un

In un quaderno scolastico, della fine anni Venti, uno tra i molti del Fondo Materiali scolastici dell’Archivio storico Indire, un alunno scrive:... sventolarono il nostro

Visitors jumped up and so did page views, less time spent on the website is also a consequence of people reading downloaded deliverables offline.... Page

Il Risk management, perché sia efficace, deve interessare tutte le aree in cui l’errore si può manifestare durante il processo clinico assistenziale del paziente: solo una